SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
_________________
Nos. 21–1086 and 21–1087
_________________
WES ALLEN, ALABAMA SECRETARY OF STATE,
et al., APPELLANTS
21–1086
v.
EVAN MILLIGAN, et al.
on appeal from the united states district
court for the northern district of alabama
WES ALLEN, ALABAMA SECRETARY OF STATE,
et al., PETITIONERS
21–1087
v.
MARCUS CASTER, et al.
on writ of certiorari before judgment to the
united states court of appeals for the eleventh circuit
[June 8, 2023]
Justice Thomas, with whom Justice Gorsuch
joins, with whom Justice Barrett joins as to Parts II and III, and
with whom Justice Alito joins as to Parts II–A and II–B,
dissenting.
These cases “are yet another installment in the
‘disastrous misadventure’ of this Court’s voting rights
jurisprudence.”
Alabama Legislative Black Caucus v.
Alabama, 575 U.S. 254, 294 (2015) (Thomas, J., dissenting)
(quoting
Holder v.
Hall,
512
U.S. 874, 893 (1994) (Thomas, J., concurring in judgment)).
What distinguishes them is the uncommon clarity with which they lay
bare the gulf between our “color-blind” Constitution,
Plessy
v.
Ferguson,
163 U.S.
537, 559 (1896) (Harlan, J., dissenting), and “the consciously
segregated districting system currently being constructed in the
name of the Voting Rights Act.”
Holder, 512 U. S., at
907 (opinion of Thomas, J.). The question presented is whether §2
of the Act, as amended, requires the State of Alabama to
intentionally redraw its longstanding congressional districts so
that black voters can control a number of seats roughly
proportional to the black share of the State’s population. Section
2 demands no such thing, and, if it did, the Constitution would not
permit it.
I
At the outset, I would resolve these cases in
a way that would not require the Federal Judiciary to decide the
correct racial apportionment of Alabama’s congressional seats.
Under the statutory text, a §2 challenge must target a “voting
qualification or prerequisite to voting or standard, practice, or
procedure.” 52 U. S. C. §10301(a). I have long been
convinced that those words reach only “enactments that regulate
citizens’ access to the ballot or the processes for counting a
ballot”; they “do not include a State’s . . . choice of
one districting scheme over another.”
Holder, 512
U. S., at 945 (opinion of Thomas, J.). “Thus, §2 cannot
provide a basis for invalidating any district.”
Abbott v.
Perez, 585 U. S. ___, ___ (2018) (Thomas, J.,
concurring) (slip op., at 1).
While I will not repeat all the arguments that
led me to this conclusion nearly three decades ago, see
Holder, 512 U. S., at 914–930 (opinion concurring in
judgment), the Court’s belated appeal to the statutory text is not
persuasive. See
ante, at 31–32. Whatever words like
“practice” and “procedure” are capable of meaning in a vacuum, the
prohibitions
of §2 apply to practices and procedures that
affect “voting” and “the right . . . to vote.” §10301(a).
“Vote” and “voting” are defined terms under the Act, and the Act’s
definition plainly focuses on ballot access and counting:
“The terms ‘vote’ or ‘voting’ shall
include all action necessary to make a vote effective in any
primary, special, or general election, including, but not limited
to, registration, listing pursuant to this chapter, or other action
required by law prerequisite to voting, casting a ballot, and
having such ballot counted properly and included in the appropriate
totals of votes cast with respect to candidates for public or party
office and propositions for which votes are received in an
election.” §10310(c)(1).
In enacting the original Voting Rights Act in
1965, Congress copied this definition almost verbatim from Title VI
of the Civil Rights Act of 1960—a law designed to protect access to
the ballot in jurisdictions with patterns or practices of denying
such access based on race, and which cannot be construed to
authorize so-called vote-dilution claims. See 74Stat. 91–92
(codified in relevant part at 52 U. S. C. §10101(e)).
Title I of the Civil Rights Act of 1964, which cross-referenced the
1960 Act’s definition of “vote,” likewise protects ballot access
alone and cannot be read to address vote dilution. See 78Stat. 241
(codified in relevant part at 52 U. S. C. §10101(a)).
Tellingly, the 1964 Act also used the words “standard, practice, or
procedure” to refer specifically to voting qualifications for
individuals and the actions of state and local officials in
administering such requirements.[
1] Our entire enterprise of applying §2 to districting
rests on systematic neglect of these statutory antecedents and,
more broadly, of the ballot-access focus of the 1960s’
voting-rights struggles. See,
e.g.,
Brnovich v.
Democratic National Committee, 594 U. S. ___, ___
(2021) (slip op., at 2) (describing the “notorious methods” by
which, prior to the
Voting Rights Act, States and localities
deprived black Americans of the ballot: “poll taxes, literacy
tests, property qualifications, white primaries, and grandfather
clauses” (alterations and internal quotation marks
omitted)).[
2]
Moreover, the majority drastically overstates
the
stare decisis support for applying §2 to single-member
districting plans like the one at issue here.[
3] As the majority implicitly acknowledges, this
Court has only applied §2 to invalidate one single-member district
in one case. See
League of United Latin American Citizens v.
Perry,
548 U.S.
399, 447 (2006) (
LULAC) (opinion of Kennedy, J.). And no
party in that case argued that the plaintiffs’ vote-dilution claim
was not cognizable. As for
Growe v.
Emison,
507 U.S.
25 (1993), it held only that the threshold preconditions for
challenging multimember and at-large plans must limit challenges to
single-member districts with
at least the same force, as
“[i]t would be peculiar [if] a vote-dilution challenge to the (more
dangerous) multimember district require[d] a higher threshold
showing than a vote-fragmentation challenge to a single-member
district.”
Id., at 40.
Growe did not consider (or,
thus, reject) an argument that §2 does not apply to single-member
districts.
In any event,
stare decisis should be no
barrier to reconsidering a line of cases that “was based on a
flawed method of statutory construction from its inception,” has
proved incapable of principled application after nearly four
decades of experience, and puts federal courts in the business of
“methodically carving the country into racially designated
electoral districts.”
Holder, 512 U. S., at 945
(opinion of Thomas, J.). This Court has “never applied
stare
decisis mechanically to prohibit overruling our earlier
decisions determining the meaning of statutes,” and it should not
do so here.
Monell v.
New York City Dept. of Social
Servs.,
436 U.S.
658, 695 (1978).
Stare decisis did not save “separate
but equal,” despite its repeated reaffirmation in this Court and
the pervasive reliance States had placed upon it for decades. See,
e.g., Brief for Appellees in
Brown v.
Board of
Education, O. T. 1953, No. 1, pp. 18–30. It should
not rescue modern-day forms of
de jure racial
balkanization—which, as these cases show, is exactly where our §2
vote-dilution jurisprudence has led.[
4]
II
Even if §2 applies here, however, Alabama
should prevail. The District Court found that Alabama’s
congressional districting map “dilutes” black residents’ votes
because, while it is
possible to draw two majority-black
districts, Alabama’s map only has one.[
5] But the critical question in all vote-dilution cases
is: “Diluted relative to what benchmark?”
Gonzalez v.
Aurora, 535 F.3d 594, 598 (CA7 2008) (Easterbrook,
C. J.). Neither the District Court nor the majority has any
defensible answer. The text of §2 and the logic of vote-dilution
claims require a meaningfully race-neutral benchmark, and no
race-neutral benchmark can justify the District Court’s finding of
vote dilution in these cases. The only benchmark that can justify
it—and the one that the District Court demonstrably applied—is the
decidedly nonneutral benchmark of proportional allocation of
political power based on race.
A
As we have long recognized, “the very concept
of vote dilution implies—and, indeed, necessitates—the existence of
an ‘undiluted’ practice against which the fact of dilution may be
measured.”
Reno v.
Bossier Parish School Bd.,
520 U.S.
471, 480 (1997). In a challenge to a districting plan, a court
must be able to compare a State’s enacted plan with “a
hypothetical, undiluted plan,”
ibid., ascertained by an
“objective and workable standard.”
Holder, 512 U. S.,
at 881 (plurality opinion); see also
id., at 887 (opinion of
O’Connor, J.) (noting the “general agreement” on this point).
To be sure, it is no easy task to identify an
objective, “undiluted” benchmark against which to judge a
districting plan. As we recently held in the analogous context of
partisan gerrymandering, “federal courts are not equipped to
apportion political power as a matter of fairness.”
Rucho v.
Common Cause, 588 U. S. ___, ___ (2019) (slip op., at
17). Yet §2 vote-dilution cases require nothing less. If §2
prohibited only intentional racial discrimination, there would be
no difficulty in finding a clear and workable rule of decision. But
the “results test” that Congress wrote into §2 to supersede
Mobile v.
Bolden,
446 U.S.
55 (1980), eschews intent as the criterion of liability. See
Bossier Parish School Bd., 520 U. S., at 482.
Accordingly, a §2 vote-dilution claim does not simply “as[k]
. . . for the elimination of a racial classification.”
Rucho, 588 U. S., at ___ (slip op., at 21). It asks,
instead, “for a fair share of political power and influence, with
all the justiciability conundrums that entails.”
Ibid.
Nevertheless, if §2 applies to single-member districts, we must
accept that some “objective and workable standard for choosing a
reasonable benchmark” exists; otherwise, single-member districts
“cannot be challenged as dilutive under §2.”
Holder, 512
U. S., at 881 (plurality opinion).
Given the diverse circumstances of different
jurisdictions, it would be fanciful to expect a one-size-fits-all
definition of the appropriate benchmark. Cf.
Thornburg v.
Gingles,
478 U.S.
30, 79 (1986) (explaining that the vote-dilution inquiry “is
peculiarly dependent upon the facts of each case and requires an
intensely local appraisal” (citation and internal quotation marks
omitted)). One overriding principle, however, should be obvious. A
proper districting benchmark must be
race neutral: It must
not assume,
a priori, that an acceptable plan should
include any particular number or proportion of minority-controlled
districts.
I begin with §2’s text. As relevant here, §2(a)
prohibits a State from “impos[ing] or appl[ying]” any electoral
rule “in a manner which results in a denial or abridgement of the
right . . . to vote on account of race or color.”
§10301(a). Section 2(b) then provides that §2(a) is violated
“if, based on the totality of
circumstances, . . . the political processes leading to
nomination or election in the State . . . are not equally
open to participation by members of [a protected class] in that its
members have less opportunity than other members of the electorate
to participate in the political process and to elect
representatives of their choice. The extent to which members of a
protected class have been elected to office in the State
. .
Provided, That nothing in this section
establishes a right to have members of a protected class elected in
numbers equal to their proportion in the population.”
§10301(b).
As we held two Terms ago in
Brnovich, the
“equal openness” requirement is “the core” and “touchstone” of
§2(b),
with “equal opportunity” serving an ancillary
function.[
6] 594 U. S., at
___ (slip op., at 15). Relying significantly on §2(b)’s disclaimer
of a right to proportional representation, we also held that §2
does not enact a “freewheeling disparate-impact regime.”
Id., at ___, and n. 14 (slip op., at 22, and n. 14).
Brnovich further stressed the value of “benchmarks with
which . . . challenged [electoral] rule[s] can be
compared,”
id., at ___ (slip op., at 17), and that “a
meaningful comparison is essential” in judging the significance of
any challenged scheme’s racially disparate impact.
Id., at
___ (slip op., at 18). To the extent §2 applies to districting
plans, then, it requires that they be “equally open to
participation” by voters of all races, but it is not a pure
disparate-impact statute and does not guarantee proportional
representation.
In its main argument here, Alabama simply
carries these principles to their logical conclusion: Any
vote-dilution benchmark must be race neutral. See Brief for
Appellants 32–46. Whatever “equal openness” means in the context of
single-member districting, no “meaningful comparison” is possible
using a benchmark that builds in a presumption in favor of
minority-controlled districts. Indeed, any benchmark other than a
race-neutral one would render the vote-dilution inquiry
fundamentally circular, allowing courts to conclude that a
districting plan “dilutes” a minority’s voting strength “on account
of race” merely because it does not measure up to an ideal already
defined in racial terms. Such a question-begging standard would not
answer our precedents’ demand for an “
objective,”
“reasonable benchmark.”
Holder, 512 U. S., at 881
(plurality opinion) (emphasis added). Nor could any nonneutral
benchmark be reconciled with
Brnovich’s rejection of a
disparate-impact regime or the text’s disclaimer of a right to
proportional representation. 594 U. S., at ___, and n. 14
(slip op., at 22, and n. 14).
There is yet another compelling reason to insist
on a race-neutral benchmark. “The Constitution abhors
classifications based on race.”
Grutter v.
Bollinger,
539 U.S.
306, 353 (2003) (Thomas, J., concurring in part and dissenting
in part). Redistricting is no exception. “Just as the State may
not, absent extraordinary justification, segregate citizens on the
basis of race in its public parks, buses, golf courses, beaches,
and schools,” the State also “may not separate its citizens into
different voting districts on the basis of race.”
Miller v.
Johnson,
515
U.S. 900, 911 (1995) (citations omitted). “[D]istricting maps
that sort voters on the basis of race ‘ “are by their very
nature odious.” ’ ”
Wisconsin Legislature v.
Wisconsin Elections Comm’n, 595 U. S. ___, ___ (2022)
(
per curiam) (slip op., at 2) (quoting
Shaw v.
Reno,
509 U.S.
630, 643 (1993) (
Shaw I)). Accordingly, our precedents
apply strict scrutiny whenever race was “the predominant factor
motivating [the placement of] a significant number of voters within
or without a particular district,”
Miller, 515 U. S.,
at 916, or, put another way, whenever “[r]ace was the criterion
that . . . could not be compromised” in a district’s
formation.
Shaw v.
Hunt,
517
U.S. 899, 907 (1996) (
Shaw II).
Because “[r]acial gerrymandering, even for
remedial purposes, may balkanize us into competing racial factions”
and undermine “the goal of a political system in which race no
longer matters,”
Shaw I, 509 U. S., at 657, our cases
have long recognized the need to interpret §2 to avoid
“unnecessarily infus[ing] race into virtually every redistricting”
plan.
LULAC, 548 U. S., at 446 (opinion of Kennedy,
J.); accord,
Bartlett v.
Strickland,
556 U.S.
1, 21 (2009) (plurality opinion). Plainly, however, that
“infusion” is the inevitable result of any race-based benchmark.
Any interpretation of §2 that permits courts to condemn enacted
districting plans as dilutive relative to a nonneutral benchmark
“would result in a substantial increase in the number of mandatory
districts drawn with race as ‘the predominant factor motivating the
legislature’s decision,’ ” thus “ ‘raising serious
constitutional questions.’ ”
Id., at 21–22 (first
quoting
Miller, 515 U. S., at 916, then quoting
LULAC, 548 U. S., at 446). To avoid setting §2 on a
collision course with the Constitution, courts must apply a
race-neutral benchmark in assessing any claim that a districting
plan unlawfully dilutes a racial minority’s voting strength.
B
The plaintiffs in these cases seek a
“proportional allocation of political power according to race.”
Holder, 512 U. S., at 936 (opinion of Thomas, J.).
According to the 2020 census, black Alabamians account for 27.16%
of the State’s total population and 25.9% of its voting-age
population, both figures slightly less than two-sevenths. Of
Alabama’s seven existing congressional districts, one, District 7,
is majority-black.[
7] These
cases were brought to compel “the creation of
two
majority-minority congressional districts”—roughly proportional
control. 1 App. 135 (emphasis added); see also
id., at 314
(“Plaintiffs seek an order . . . ordering a congressional
redistricting plan that includes two majority-Black congressional
districts”).
Remarkably, the majority fails to acknowledge
that two minority-controlled districts would mean proportionality,
or even that black Alabamians are about two-sevenths of the State.
Yet that context is critical to the issues before us, not least
because it explains the extent of the racial sorting the
plaintiffs’ goal would require. “[A]s a matter of mathematics,”
single-member districting “tends to deal out representation far
short of proportionality to virtually
all minorities, from
environmentalists in Alaska to Republicans in Massachusetts.” M.
Duchin & D. Spencer, Models, Race, and the Law, 130 Yale
L. J. Forum 744, 752 (2021) (Duchin & Spencer). As such,
creating two majority-black districts would require Alabama to
aggressively “sort voters on the basis of race.”
Wisconsin
Legislature, 595 U. S., at ___ (slip op., at 2).
The plaintiffs’ 11 illustrative maps make that
clear. All 11 maps refashion existing District 2 into a
majority-black district while preserving the current black majority
in District 7. They all follow the same approach: Starting with
majority-black areas of populous Montgomery County, they
expand District 2 east and west to encompass
predominantly majority-black areas throughout the rural “Black
Belt.” In the process, the plans are careful to leave enough of the
Black Belt for District 7 to maintain its black majority. Then—and
critically—the plans have District 2 extend a southwestern tendril
into Mobile County to capture a dense, high-population
majority-black cluster in urban Mobile.[
8] See Supp. App. 184, 186, 188, 190, 193, 195, 197, 199,
201, 203; see also
id., at 149.
Those black Mobilians currently reside in the
urban heart of District 1. For 50 years, District 1 has occupied
the southwestern pocket of Alabama, consisting of the State’s two
populous Gulf Coast counties (Mobile and Baldwin) as well as some
less populous areas to the immediate north and east. See
id., at 205–211. It is indisputable that the Gulf Coast
region is the sort of community of interest that the Alabama
Legislature might reasonably think a congressional district should
be built around. It contains Alabama’s only coastline, its fourth
largest city, and the Port of Mobile. Its physical geography runs
north along the Alabama and Mobile Rivers, whose paths District 1
follows. Its economy is tied to the Gulf—to shipping, shipbuilding,
tourism, and commercial fishing. See Brief for Coastal Alabama
Partnership as
Amicus Curiae 13–15.
But, for the plaintiffs to secure their
majority-black District 2, this longstanding, compact, and
eminently sensible district must be radically transformed. In the
Gulf Coast region, the newly drawn District 1 would retain only the
majority-white areas that District 2 did not absorb on its path to
Mobile’s large majority-black population. To make up the lost
population, District 1 would have to extend eastward through
largely majority-white rural counties along the length of Alabama’s
border with the Florida panhandle. The plaintiffs do not assert
that white residents on the Gulf Coast have anything special in
common with white residents in those communities, and the District
Court made no such finding. The plaintiffs’ maps would thus reduce
District 1 to the leftover white communities of the southern fringe
of the State, its shape and constituents defined almost entirely by
the need to make District 2 majority-black while also retaining a
majority-black District 7.
The plaintiffs’ mapmaking experts left little
doubt that their plans prioritized race over neutral districting
criteria. Dr. Moon Duchin, who devised four of the plans, testified
that achieving “two majority-black districts” was a “nonnegotiable
principl[e]” in her eyes, a status shared only by our precedents’
“population balance” requirement. 2 App. 634; see also
id.,
at 665, 678. Only “after” those two “nonnegotiable[s]” were
satisfied did Dr. Duchin then give lower priority to “contiguity”
and “compactness.”
Id., at 634. The architect of the other
seven maps, William Cooper, considered “minority voting strengt[h]”
a “traditional redistricting principl[e]” in its own right,
id., at 591, and treated “the minority population in and of
itself ” as the paramount community of interest in his plans,
id., at 601.
Statistical evidence also underscored the
illustrative maps’ extreme racial sorting. Another of the
plaintiffs’ experts, Dr. Kosuke Imai, computer generated 10,000
districting plans using a race-blind algorithm programmed to
observe several objective districting criteria. Supp. App. 58–59.
None of those plans contained even one majority-black district.
Id., at 61. Dr. Imai generated another 20,000 plans using
the same algorithm, but with the additional constraint that they
must contain at least one majority- black district; none of those
plans contained a second majority-black district, or even a second
district with a black voting-age population above 40%.
Id.,
at 54, 67, 71–72. In a similar vein, Dr. Duchin testified about an
academic study in which she had randomly “generated 2 million
districting plans for Alabama” using a race-neutral algorithm that
gave priority to compactness and contiguity. 2 App. 710; see Duchin
& Spencer 765. She “found some [plans] with one majority-black
district, but never found a second . . . majority-black
district in 2 million attempts.” 2 App. 710. “[T]hat it is hard to
draw two majority-black districts by accident,” Dr. Duchin
explained, “show[ed] the importance of doing so on purpose.”
Id., at 714.[
9]
The plurality of Justices who join Part III–B–I
of The Chief Justice’s opinion appear to agree that the plaintiffs
could not prove the first precondition of their statewide
vote-dilution claim—that black Alabamians could constitute a
majority in two “reasonably configured” districts,
Wisconsin
Legislature, 595 U. S., at ___ (slip op., at 3)—by drawing
an illustrative map in which race was predominant. See
ante,
at 25. That should be the end of these cases, as the illustrative
maps here are palpable racial gerrymanders. The plaintiffs’ experts
clearly applied “express racial target[s]” by setting out to create
50%-plus majority-black districts in both Districts 2 and 7.
Bethune-Hill v.
Virginia State Bd. of Elections, 580
U.S. 178, 192 (2017). And it is impossible to conceive of
the
State adopting the illustrative maps without pursuing the same
racially motivated goals. Again, the maps’ key design features are:
(1) making District 2 majority-black by connecting black residents
in one metropolitan area (Montgomery) with parts of the rural Black
Belt and black residents in another metropolitan area (Mobile); (2)
leaving enough of the Black Belt’s majority-black rural areas for
District 7 to maintain its majority-black status; and (3) reducing
District 1 to the white remainder of the southern third of the
State.
If the State did this, we would call it a racial
gerrymander, and rightly so. We would have no difficulty
recognizing race as “the predominant factor motivating [the
placement of] significant number[s] of voters within or without”
Districts 1, 2, and 7.
Miller, 515 U. S., at 916. The
“stark splits in the racial composition of populations moved into
and out of ” Districts 1 and 2 would make that obvious.
Bethune-Hill, 580 U. S., at 192. So would the manifest
absence of any nonracial justification for the new District 1. And
so would the State’s clear intent to ensure that
both
Districts 2 and 7 hit their preordained racial targets. See
ibid. (noting that “pursu[it of] a common redistricting
policy toward multiple districts” may show predominance). That the
plan delivered proportional control for a particular minority—a
statistical anomaly that over 2 million race-blind simulations did
not yield and 20,000
race-conscious simulations did not even
approximate—would be still further confirmation.
The State could not justify such a plan simply
by arguing that it was less bizarre to the naked eye than other,
more elaborate racial gerrymanders we have encountered. See
ante, at 19–20 (discussing cases). As we held in
Miller, visual “bizarreness” is not “a necessary element of
the constitutional wrong,” only “persuasive circumstantial
evidence.” 515 U. S., at 912–913.[
10]
Nor could such a plan be explained by supposed
respect for the Black Belt. For present purposes, I accept the
District Court’s finding that the Black Belt is a significant
community of interest. But the entire black population of the Black
Belt—some 300,000 black residents, see Supp. App. 33—is too small
to provide a majority in a
single congressional district,
let alone two.[
11] The black
residents needed to populate majority-black versions of Districts 2
and 7 are overwhelmingly concentrated in the urban counties of
Jefferson (
i.e., the Birmingham metropolitan area, with
about 290,000 black residents), Mobile (about 152,000 black
residents), and Montgomery (about 134,000 black residents).
Id., at 83. Of the three, only Montgomery County is in the
Black Belt. The plaintiffs’ maps, therefore, cannot and do not
achieve their goal of two majority-black districts by “join[ing]
together” the Black Belt, as the majority seems wrongly to believe.
Ante, at 13. Rather, their majority-black districts are
anchored by three separate high-density clusters of black residents
in three separate metropolitan areas, two of them outside the Black
Belt. The Black Belt’s largely rural remainder is then
divided between the two districts to the extent needed to
fill out their population numbers with black majorities in both.
Respect for the Black Belt as a community of interest cannot
explain this approach. The only explanation is the plaintiffs’
express racial target: two majority-black districts and statewide
proportionality.
The District Court nonetheless found that race
did not predominate in the plaintiffs’ illustrative maps because
Dr. Duchin and Mr. Cooper “prioritized race only as necessary
. . . to draw two reasonably compact majority-Black
congressional districts,” as opposed to “maximiz[ing] the number of
majority-Black districts, or the BVAP [black voting-age population]
in any particular majority-Black district.”
Singleton v.
Merrill, 582 F. Supp. 3d 924, 1029–1030 (ND Ala. 2022)
(
per curiam). This reasoning shows a profound
misunderstanding of our racial-gerrymandering precedents. As
explained above, what triggers strict scrutiny is the intentional
use of a racial classification in placing “a significant number of
voters within or without a particular district.”
Miller, 515
U. S., at 916. Thus,
any plan whose predominant purpose
is to achieve a nonnegotiable, predetermined racial target in a
nonnegotiable, predetermined number of districts is a racial
gerrymander subject to strict scrutiny. The precise fraction used
as the racial target, and the number of districts it is applied to,
are irrelevant.
In affirming the District Court’s
nonpredominance finding, the plurality glosses over these plain
legal errors,[
12] and it
entirely ignores Dr. Duchin’s plans—presumably because her own
explanation of her method sounds too much like textbook racial
predominance. Compare 2 App. 634 (“[A]fter . . . what I
took to be
nonnegotiable principles of population balance
and seeking two majority-black districts,
after that,
I took contiguity as a requirement and compactness as paramount”
(emphasis added)) and
id., at 635 (“I took . . .
county integrity to take precedence over the level of [black
voting-age population]
once that level was past 50 percent”
(emphasis added)), with
Bethune-Hill, 580 U. S., at 189
(explaining that race predominates when it “ ‘was the
criterion that . . . could not be compromised,’ and
race-neutral considerations ‘came into play only after the
race-based decision had been made’ ” (quoting
Shaw II,
517 U. S., at 907)), and
Miller, 515 U. S., at 916
(explaining that race predominates when “the [mapmaker]
subordinated traditional race-neutral districting principles
. . . to racial considerations”). The plurality thus
affirms the District Court’s finding only in part and with regard
to Mr. Cooper’s plans alone.
In doing so, the plurality acts as if the only
relevant evidence were Mr. Cooper’s testimony about his own mental
state and the State’s expert’s analysis of Mr. Cooper’s maps. See
ante, at 23–24. Such a blinkered view of the issue is
unjustifiable. All 11 illustrative maps follow the same approach to
creating two majority-black districts. The essential design
features of Mr. Cooper’s maps are indistinguishable from Dr.
Duchin’s, and it is those very design features that would require
race to predominate. None of the plaintiffs’ maps could possibly be
drawn by a mapmaker who was merely “aware of,” rather than
motivated by, “racial demographics.”
Miller, 515 U. S.,
at 916. They could only ever be drawn by a mapmaker whose
predominant motive was hitting the “express racial target” of two
majority-black districts.
Bethune-Hill, 580 U. S., at
192.[
13]
The plurality endeavors in vain to blunt the
force of this obvious fact. See
ante, at 24–25. Contrary to
the plurality’s apparent understanding, nothing in
Bethune-Hill suggests that “an express racial target” is not
highly probative evidence of racial predominance. 580 U. S.,
at 192 (placing “express racial target[s]” alongside “stark splits
in the racial composition of [redistricted] populations” as
“relevant districtwide evidence”). That the
Bethune-Hill
majority “decline[d]” to act as a “ ‘court of . . .
first view,’ ” instead leaving the ultimate issue of
predominance for remand, cannot be transmuted into such an
implausible holding or, in truth, any holding at all.
Id.,
at 193.
The plurality is also mistaken that my
predominance analysis would doom every illustrative map a §2
plaintiff “ever adduced.”
Ante, at 25 (emphasis deleted).
Rather, it would mean only that—because §2 requires a race-neutral
benchmark—plaintiffs cannot satisfy their threshold burden of
showing a reasonably configured alternative plan with a proposal
that could only be viewed as a racial gerrymander if enacted by the
State. This rule would not bar a showing, in an appropriate case,
that a State could create an additional majority-minority district
through a reasonable redistricting process in which race did not
predominate. It would, on the other hand, screen out efforts to use
§2 to push racially proportional districting to the limits of what
a State’s geography and demography make possible—the approach taken
by the illustrative maps here.
C
The foregoing analysis should be enough to
resolve these cases: If the plaintiffs have not shown that Alabama
could create two majority-black districts without resorting to a
racial gerrymander, they cannot have shown that Alabama’s
one-majority-black-district map “dilutes” black Alabamians’ voting
strength relative to any meaningfully race-neutral benchmark. The
inverse, however, is not true: Even if it were possible to regard
the illustrative maps as not requiring racial predominance, it
would not necessarily follow that a two-majority-black-district map
was an appropriate benchmark. All that might follow is that the
illustrative maps were reasonably configured—in other words, that
they were consistent with some reasonable application of
traditional districting criteria in which race did not predominate.
See
LULAC, 548 U. S., at 433. But, in virtually all
jurisdictions, there are countless possible districting schemes
that could be considered reasonable in that sense. The mere fact
that a plaintiff ’s illustrative map is
one of them
cannot justify making it the benchmark against which other plans
should be judged. Cf.
Rucho, 588 U. S., at ___–___
(slip op., at 19–20) (explaining the lack of judicially manageable
standards for evaluating the relative fairness of different
applications of traditional districting criteria).
That conceptual gap—between “reasonable” and
“benchmark”—is highly relevant here. Suppose, for argument’s sake,
that Alabama
reasonably could decide to create two
majority-black districts by (1) connecting Montgomery’s black
residents with Mobile’s black residents, (2) dividing up the rural
parts of the Black Belt between that district and another district
with its population core in the majority-black parts of the
Birmingham area, and (3) accepting the extreme disruption to
District 1 and the Gulf Coast that this approach would require. The
plaintiffs prefer that approach because it allows the creation of
two majority-black districts, which they think Alabama should have.
But even if that approach were reasonable, there is hardly any
compelling race-neutral reason to elevate such a plan to a
benchmark against which all other plans must be measured.
Nothing in Alabama’s geography or demography makes it clearly the
best way, or even a particularly attractive way, to draw three of
seven equally populous districts. The State has obvious legitimate,
race-neutral reasons to prefer its own map—most notably, its
interest in “preserving the cores of prior districts” and the Gulf
Coast community of interest in District 1.
Karcher v.
Daggett,
462 U.S.
725, 740 (1983). And even
discounting those interests
would not yield a race-neutral case for treating the plaintiffs’
approach as a suitable benchmark: Absent core retention, there is
no apparent race-neutral reason to insist that District 7 remain a
majority-black district uniting Birmingham’s majority-black
neighborhoods with majority-black rural areas in the Black
Belt.
Finally, it is surely probative that over 2
million race-neutral simulations did not yield a single plan with
two majority-black districts, and even 20,000 simulations with a
one-majority-black-district floor did not yield a second district
with a black voting-age population over 40%. If any plan with two
majority-black districts would be an “out-out-out-outlier” within
the likely universe of race-neutral districting plans,
Rucho, 588 U. S., at ___ (Kagan, J., dissenting) (slip
op., at 19), it is hard to see how the mere possibility of drawing
two majority-black districts could show that a one-district map
diluted black Alabamians’ votes relative to any appropriate
benchmark.[
14]
D
Given all this, by what benchmark did the
District Court find that Alabama’s enacted plan was dilutive? The
answer is as simple as it is unlawful: The District Court applied a
benchmark of proportional control based on race. To be sure, that
benchmark was camouflaged by the elaborate vote-dilution framework
we have inherited from
Gingles. But nothing else in that
framework or in the District Court’s reasoning supplies an
alternative benchmark capable of explaining the District Court’s
bottom line: that Alabama’s one-majority-black-district map dilutes
black voters’ fair share of political power.
Under
Gingles, the majority explains,
there are three “preconditions” to a vote-dilution claim: (1) the
relevant “minority group must be sufficiently large and
geographically compact to constitute a majority in a reasonably
configured district”; (2) the minority group must be “politically
cohesive”; and (3) the majority group must “vot[e] sufficiently as
a bloc to enable it to defeat the minority’s preferred
candidate[s].”
Ante, at 10 (alterations and internal
quotation marks omitted). If these preconditions are satisfied,
Gingles instructs courts to “consider the totality of the
circumstances and to determine, based upon a searching practical
evaluation of the past and present reality, whether the political
process is equally open to minority voters.” 478 U. S., at 79
(citation and internal quotation marks omitted).
The majority gives the impression that, in
applying this framework, the District Court merely followed a set
of well-settled, determinate legal principles. But it is widely
acknowledged that “
Gingles and its progeny have engendered
considerable disagreement and uncertainty regarding the nature and
contours of a vote dilution claim,” with commentators “noting the
lack of any ‘authoritative resolution of the basic questions one
would need to answer to make sense of [§2’s] results test.’ ”
Merrill v.
Milligan, 595 U. S. ___, ___–___
(2022) (Roberts, C. J., dissenting from grant of applications for
stays) (slip op., at 1–2) (quoting C. Elmendorf, Making Sense of
Section 2: Of Biased Votes, Unconstitutional Elections, and Common
Law Statutes, 160 U. Pa. L. Rev. 377, 389 (2012)). If there is
any “area of law notorious for its many unsolved puzzles,” this is
it. J. Chen & N. Stephanopoulos, The Race-Blind Future of
Voting Rights, 130 Yale L. J. 862, 871 (2021); see also Duchin
& Spencer 758 (“Vote dilution on the basis of group membership
is a crucial instance of the lack of a prescribed ideal”).
The source of this confusion is fundamental:
Quite simply, we have never succeeded in translating the
Gingles framework into an objective and workable method of
identifying the undiluted benchmark. The second and third
preconditions are all but irrelevant to the task. They essentially
collapse into one question: Is voting racially polarized such that
minority-preferred candidates consistently lose to
majority-preferred ones? See
Gingles, 478 U. S., at 51.
Even if the answer is yes, that tells a court nothing about “how
hard it ‘should’ be for minority voters to elect their preferred
candidates under an acceptable system.”
Id., at 88
(O’Connor, J., concurring in judgment). Perhaps an acceptable
system is one in which the minority simply cannot elect its
preferred candidates; it is, after all, a minority. Rejecting that
outcome as “dilutive” requires a value judgment relative to a
benchmark that polarization alone cannot provide.
The first
Gingles precondition is only
marginally more useful. True, the benchmark in a redistricting
challenge must be “a hypothetical, undiluted plan,”
Bossier
Parish School Bd., 520 U. S., at 480, and the first
precondition at least requires plaintiffs to identify
some
hypothetical alternative plan. Yet that alternative plan need only
be “reasonably configured,” and—as explained above—to say that a
plan is
reasonable is a far cry from establishing an
objective standard of fairness.
That leaves only the
Gingles framework’s
final stage: the totality-of-circumstances determination whether a
State’s “political process is equally open to minority voters.” 478
U. S., at 79. But this formulation is mere verbiage unless one
knows what an “equally open” system should look like—in other
words, what the benchmark is. And, our cases offer no substantive
guidance on how to identify the undiluted benchmark at the totality
stage. The best they have to offer is a grab bag of amorphous
“factors”—widely known as the Senate factors, after the Senate
Judiciary Committee Report accompanying the 1982 amendments to
§2—that
Gingles said “typically may be relevant to a §2
claim.” See
id., at 44–45. Those factors, however, amount to
no more than “a list of possible considerations that might be
consulted by a court attempting to develop a
gestalt view of
the political and racial climate in a jurisdiction.”
Holder,
512 U. S., at 938 (opinion of Thomas, J.). Such a
gestalt view is far removed from the necessary benchmark of
a hypothetical, undiluted districting plan.
To see this, one need only consider the District
Court’s use of the Senate factors here. See 582 F. Supp. 3d,
at 1018–1024. The court began its totality-stage analysis by
reiterating what nobody disputes: that voting in Alabama is
racially polarized, with black voters overwhelmingly preferring
Democrats and white voters largely preferring Republicans. To rebut
the State’s argument that this pattern is attributable to politics,
not race
per se, the court noted that Donald Trump (who
is white) prevailed over Ben Carson (who is black) in the 2016
Republican Presidential primary. Next, the court observed that
black candidates rarely win statewide elections in Alabama and that
black state legislators overwhelmingly come from majority-minority
districts. The court then reviewed Alabama’s history of racial
discrimination, noted other voting-rights cases in which the State
was found liable, and cataloged socioeconomic disparities between
black and white Alabamians in everything from car ownership to
health insurance coverage. The court attributed these disparities
“at least in part” to the State’s history of discrimination and
found that they hinder black residents from participating in
politics today, notwithstanding the fact that black and white
Alabamians register and turn out to vote at similar rates.
Id., at 1021–1022. Last, the court interpreted a handful of
comments by three white politicians as “racial campaign appeals.”
Id., at 1023–1024.
In reviewing this march through the Senate
factors, it is impossible to discern any overarching standard or
central question, only what might be called an impressionistic
moral audit of Alabama’s racial past and present. Nor is it
possible to determine any logical nexus between this audit and the
remedy ordered: a congressional districting plan in which black
Alabamians can control more than one seat. Given the District
Court’s finding that two reasonably configured majority-black
districts could be drawn, would Alabama’s one-district map have
been acceptable if Ben Carson had won the 2016 primary, or if a
greater number of black Alabamians owned cars?
The idea that such factors could explain the
District Court’s judgment line is absurd. The plaintiffs’ claims
pose one simple question: What is the “right” number of Alabama’s
congressional seats that black voters who support Democrats
“should” control? Neither the Senate factors nor the
Gingles
framework as a whole offers any principled answer.
In reality, the limits of the
Gingles
preconditions and the aimlessness of the totality-of-circumstances
inquiry left the District Court only one obvious and readily
administrable option: a benchmark of “allocation of seats in direct
proportion to the minority group’s percentage in the population.”
Holder, 512 U. S., at 937 (opinion of Thomas, J.).
True, as disussed above, that benchmark is impossible to square
with what the majority calls §2(b)’s “robust disclaimer against
proportionality,”
ante, at 5, and it runs headlong into
grave constitutional problems. See
Parents Involved in Community
Schools v.
Seattle School Dist. No. 1,
551 U.S.
701, 730 (2007) (plurality opinion). Nonetheless, the intuitive
pull of proportionality is undeniable. “Once one accepts the
proposition that the effectiveness of votes is measured in terms of
the control of seats, the core of any vote dilution claim” “is
inherently based on ratios between the numbers of the minority in
the population and the numbers of seats controlled,” and there is
no more logical ratio than direct proportionality.
Holder,
512 U. S., at 902 (opinion of Thomas, J.). Combine that
intuitive appeal with the “lack of any better alternative”
identified in our case law to date,
id., at 937, and we
should not be surprised to learn that proportionality generally
explains the results of §2 cases after the
Gingles
preconditions are satisfied. See E. Katz, M. Aisenbrey, A. Baldwin,
E. Cheuse, & A. Weisbrodt, Documenting Discrimination in
Voting: Judicial Findings Under Section 2 of the Voting Rights Act
Since 1982, 39 U. Mich. J. L. Reform 643, 730–732 (2006)
(surveying lower court cases and finding a near-perfect correlation
between proportionality findings and liability results).
Thus, in the absence of an alternative
benchmark, the vote-dilution inquiry has a strong and demonstrated
tendency to collapse into a rough two-part test: (1) Does the
challenged districting plan give the relevant minority group
control of a proportional share of seats? (2) If not, has the
plaintiff shown that some reasonably configured districting plan
could better approximate proportional control? In this approach,
proportionality is the ultimate benchmark, and the first
Gingles precondition becomes a proxy for whether that
benchmark is reasonably attainable in practice.
Beneath all the trappings of the
Gingles
framework, that two-part test describes how the District Court
applied §2 here. The gravitational force of proportionality is
obvious throughout its opinion. At the front end, the District
Court even built proportionality into its understanding of
Gingles’ first precondition, finding the plaintiffs’
illustrative maps to be reasonably configured in part
because they “provide[d] a number of majority-Black
districts . . . roughly proportional to the Black
percentage of the population.” 582 F. Supp. 3d, at 1016. At
the back end, the District Court concluded its “totality” analysis
by revisiting proportionality and finding that it “weigh[ed]
decidedly in favor of the plaintiffs.”
Id., at 1025. While
the District Court disclaimed giving overriding significance to
proportionality, the fact remains that nothing else in its
reasoning provides a logical nexus to its finding of a districting
wrong and a need for a districting remedy. Finally, as if to leave
no doubt about its implicit benchmark, the court admonished the
State that “any remedial plan will need to include two districts in
which Black voters either comprise a voting-age majority or
something quite close.”
Id., at 1033. In sum, the District
Court’s thinly disguised benchmark was proportionality: Black
Alabamians are about two-sevenths of the State’s population, so
they should control two of the State’s seven congressional
seats.
That was error—perhaps an understandable error
given the limitations of the
Gingles framework, but error
nonetheless. As explained earlier, any principled application of §2
to cases such as these requires a meaningfully race-neutral
benchmark. The benchmark cannot be an
a priori thumb on
the scale for racially proportional control.
E
The majority opinion does not acknowledge the
District Court’s express proportionality-based reasoning. That
omission is of a piece with its earlier noted failures to
acknowledge the well-known indeterminacy of the
Gingles
framework, that black Alabamians are about two-sevenths of the
State’s population, and that the plaintiffs here are thus seeking
statewide proportionality. Through this pattern of omissions, the
majority obscures the burning question in these cases. The District
Court’s vote-dilution finding can be justified only by a racially
loaded benchmark—specifically, a benchmark of proportional control
based on race. Is that the benchmark the statute demands? The
majority fails to confront this question head on, and it studiously
avoids mentioning anything that would require it to do so.
The same nonresponsiveness infects the
majority’s analysis, which is largely devoted to rebutting an
argument nobody makes. Contrary to the majority’s telling, Alabama
does not equate the “race-neutral benchmark” with “the median or
average number of majority-minority districts” in a large
computer-generated set of race-blind districting plans.
Ante, at 15. The State’s argument for a race-neutral
benchmark is rooted in the text of §2, the logic of vote- dilution
claims, and the constitutional problems with any nonneutral
benchmark. See Brief for Appellants 32–46. It then relies on the
computer evidence in these cases, among other facts, to argue that
the plaintiffs have not shown dilution relative to any race-neutral
benchmark. See
id., at 54–56. But the idea that
“race-neutral benchmark”
means the composite average of many
computer-generated plans is the majority’s alone.
After thus straw-manning Alabama’s arguments at
the outset, the majority muddles its own response. In a perfunctory
footnote, it disclaims any holding that “algorithmic map making”
evidence “is categorically irrelevant” in §2 cases.
Ante, at
28, n. 8. That conclusion, however, is the obvious implication
of the majority’s reasoning and rhetoric. See
ante, at 27
(decrying a “map-comparison test” as “flawed in its fundamentals”
even if it involves concededly “adequate comparators”); see also
ante, at 17–18 (stating that the “focu[s]” of §2 analysis is
“on the specific illustrative maps that a plaintiff adduces,”
leaving unstated the implication that other algorithmically
generated maps are irrelevant). The majority in effect, if not in
word, thus forecloses any meaningful use of computer evidence to
help locate the undiluted benchmark.
There are two critical problems with this fiat.
The first, which the majority seems to recognize yet fails to
resolve, is that excluding such computer evidence from view cannot
be reconciled with §2’s command to consider “the totality of
circumstances.”[
15]
Second—and more fundamentally—the reasons that the majority gives
for downplaying the relevance of computer evidence would more
logically support a holding that there is no judicially manageable
way of applying §2’s results test to single-member districts. The
majority waxes about the “myriad considerations” that go into
districting, the “difficult, contestable choices” those
considerations require, and how “[n]othing in §2 provides an
answer” to the question of how well any given algorithm
approximates the correct benchmark.
Ante, at 27–28 (internal
quotation marks omitted). In the end, it concludes, “Section 2
cannot require courts to judge a contest of computers” in which
“there is no reliable way to determine who wins, or even where the
finish line is.”
Ante, at 29.
The majority fails to recognize that
whether vote-dilution claims require an undiluted benchmark
is not up for debate. If §2 applies to single-member districting
plans, courts cannot dispense with an undiluted benchmark for
comparison, ascertained by an objective and workable method.
Bossier Parish School Bd., 520 U. S., at 480;
Holder, 512 U. S., at 881 (plurality opinion). Of
course, I would be the last person to deny that defining the
undiluted benchmark is difficult. See
id., at 892 (opinion
of Thomas, J.) (arguing that it “immerse[s] the federal courts in a
hopeless project of weighing questions of political theory”). But
the “myriad considerations” and “[a]nswerless questions” the
majority frets about,
ante, at 27, 29, are inherent in the
very enterprise of applying §2 to single-member districts.
Everything the majority says about the difficulty of defining the
undiluted benchmark
with computer evidence applies with
equal or greater force to the task of defining it
without
such evidence. At their core, the majority’s workability concerns
are an isolated demand for rigor against the backdrop of a legal
regime that has long been “ ‘inherently standardless,’ ”
and must remain so until the Court either discovers a principled
and objective method of identifying the undiluted benchmark,
Holder, 512 U. S., at 885 (plurality opinion), or
abandons this enterprise altogether, see
id., at 945
(opinion of Thomas, J.).
Ultimately, the majority has very little to say
about the appropriate benchmark. What little it does say suggests
that the majority sees no real alternative to the District Court’s
proportional-control benchmark, though it appears unwilling to say
so outright. For example, in a nod to the statutory text and its
“equal openness” requirement, the majority asserts that “[a]
district is not equally open . . . when minority voters
face—unlike their majority peers—bloc voting along racial lines,
arising against the backdrop of substantial racial discrimination
within the State, that renders a minority vote unequal to a vote by
a nonminority voter.”
Ante, at 17. But again, we have held
that dilution cannot be shown without an objective, undiluted
benchmark, and this verbiage offers no guidance for how to
determine it.[
16] Later, the
majority asserts that “the
Gingles framework itself imposes
meaningful constraints on proportionality.”
Ante, at 18–19.
But the only constraint on proportionality the majority articulates
is that it is often
difficult to achieve—which, quite
obviously, is no principled limitation at all.
Ante, at
20–22.
Thus, the end result of the majority’s reasoning
is no different from the District Court’s: The ultimate benchmark
is a racially proportional allocation of seats, and the main
question on which liability turns is whether a closer approximation
to proportionality is possible under any reasonable application of
traditional districting criteria.[
17] This approach, moreover, is consistent with how the
majority describes the role of plaintiffs’ illustrative maps, as
well as an unjustified practical asymmetry to which its rejection
of computer evidence gives rise. Courts are to “focu[s]
. . . on the specific illustrative maps that a plaintiff
adduces,”
ante, at 17–18, by which the majority means that
courts should
not “focu[s]” on statistical evidence showing
those maps to be outliers. Thus, plaintiffs may use an algorithm to
generate any number of maps that meet specified districting
criteria and a preferred racial target; then, they need only
produce one of those maps to “sho[w] it is
possible that the
State’s map” is dilutive
. Ante, at 18 (emphasis in
original). But the State may not use algorithmic evidence to
suggest that the plaintiffs’ map is an unsuitable benchmark for
comparison—not even, apparently, if it can prove that the
illustrative map is an outlier among “billion[s]” or “trillion[s]”
of concededly “adequate comparators.”
Ante, at 27, 29; see
also
ante, at 29 (rejecting sampling algorithms). This
arbitrary restriction amounts to a thumb on the scale for §2
plaintiffs—an unearned presumption that any “reasonable” map they
put forward constitutes a benchmark against which the State’s map
can be deemed dilutive. And, once the comparison is framed in that
way, the only workable rule of decision is proportionality. See
Holder, 512 U. S., at 941–943 (opinion of Thomas,
J.).
By affirming the District Court, the majority
thus approves its benchmark of proportional control limited only by
feasibility, and it entrenches the most perverse tendencies of our
vote-dilution jurisprudence. It guarantees that courts will
continue to approach vote-dilution claims just as the District
Court here did: with no principled way of determining how many
seats a minority “should” control and with a strong temptation to
bless every incremental step toward a racially proportional
allocation that plaintiffs can pass off as consistent with any
reasonable map.
III
As noted earlier, the Court has long
recognized the need to avoid interpretations of §2 that
“ ‘would unnecessarily infuse race into virtually every
redistricting, raising serious constitutional questions.’ ”
Bartlett, 556 U. S., at 21 (plurality opinion) (quoting
LULAC, 548 U. S., at 446 (opinion of Kennedy, J.)).
Today, however, by approving the plaintiffs’ racially gerrymandered
maps as reasonably configured, refusing to ground §2 vote-dilution
claims in a race-neutral benchmark, and affirming a vote-dilution
finding that can only be justified by a benchmark of proportional
control, the majority holds, in substance, that race belongs in
virtually every redistricting. It thus drives headlong into the
very constitutional problems that the Court has long sought to
avoid. The result of this collision is unmistakable: If the
District Court’s application of §2 was correct as a statutory
matter, §2 is unconstitutional as applied here.
Because the Constitution “restricts
consideration of race and the [Voting Rights Act] demands
consideration of race,”
Abbott, 585 U. S., at ___ (slip
op., at 4), strict scrutiny is implicated wherever, as here, §2 is
applied to require a State to adopt or reject any districting plan
on the basis of race. See
Bartlett, 556 U. S., at 21–22
(plurality opinion). At this point, it is necessary to confront
directly one of the more confused notions inhabiting our
redistricting jurisprudence. In several cases, we have “assumed”
that compliance with §2 of the Voting Rights Act could be a
compelling state interest, before proceeding to
reject
race-predominant plans or districts as insufficiently tailored to
that asserted interest. See,
e.g.,
Wisconsin
Legislature, 595 U. S., at ___ (slip op., at 3);
Cooper v.
Harris, 581 U.S. 285, 292 (2017);
Shaw
II, 517 U. S., at 915;
Miller, 515 U. S., at
921. But we have never applied this assumption to
uphold a
districting plan that would otherwise violate the Constitution, and
the slightest reflection on first principles should make clear why
it would be problematic to do so.[
18] The Constitution is supreme over statutes, not vice
versa.
Marbury v.
Madison, 1 Cranch 137, 178 (1803).
Therefore, if complying with a federal statute would require a
State to engage in unconstitutional racial discrimination, the
proper conclusion is not that the statute excuses the State’s
discrimination, but that the statute is invalid.
If Congress has any power at all to require
States to sort voters into congressional districts based on race,
that power must flow from its authority to “enforce” the Fourteenth
and Fifteenth Amendments “by appropriate legislation.” Amdt. 14,
§5; Amdt. 15, §2. Since Congress in 1982 replaced intent with
effects as the criterion of liability, however, “a violation of §2
is no longer
a fortiori a violation of ” either
Amendment.
Bossier Parish School Bd., 520 U. S., at
482. Thus, §2 can be justified only under Congress’ power to “enact
reasonably prophylactic legislation to deter constitutional harm.”
Allen v.
Cooper, 589 U. S. ___, ___ (2020) (slip
op., at 11) (alteration and internal quotation marks omitted); see
City of Boerne v.
Flores,
521
U.S. 507, 517–529 (1997). Because Congress’ prophylactic-
enforcement authority is “remedial, rather than substantive,”
“[t]here must be a congruence and proportionality between the
injury to be prevented or remedied and the means adopted to that
end.”[
19]
Id., at
520. Congress’ chosen means, moreover, must “ ‘consist with
the letter and spirit of the constitution.’ ”
Shelby
County v.
Holder,
570 U.S.
529, 555 (2013) (quoting
McCulloch v.
Maryland, 4
Wheat. 316, 421 (1819)); accord,
Miller, 515 U. S., at
927.
Here, as with everything else in our
vote-dilution jurisprudence, the task of sound analysis is
encumbered by the lack of clear principles defining §2 liability in
districting. It is awkward to examine the “congruence” and
“proportionality” of a statutory rule whose very meaning exists in
a perpetual state of uncertainty. The majority makes clear,
however, that the primary factual predicate of a vote-dilution
claim is “bloc voting along racial lines” that results in
majority-preferred candidates defeating minority-preferred ones.
Ante, at 17; accord,
Gingles, 478 U. S., at 48
(“The theoretical basis for [vote-dilution claims] is that where
minority and majority voters consistently prefer different
candidates, the majority, by virtue of its numerical superiority,
will regularly defeat the choices of minority voters”). And, as I
have shown, the remedial logic with which the District Court’s
construction of §2 addresses that “wrong” rests on a
proportional-control benchmark limited only by feasibility. Thus,
the relevant statutory rule may be approximately stated as follows:
If voting is racially polarized in a jurisdiction, and if there
exists any more or less reasonably configured districting plan that
would enable the minority group to constitute a majority in a
number of districts roughly proportional to its share of the
population, then the jurisdiction must ensure that its districting
plan includes that number of majority-minority districts “or
something quite close.”[
20]
582 F. Supp. 3d, at 1033. Thus construed and applied, §2 is
not congruent and proportional to any provisions of the
Reconstruction Amendments.
To determine the congruence and proportionality
of a measure, we must begin by “identify[ing] with some precision
the scope of the constitutional right at issue.”
Board of
Trustees of Univ. of Ala. v.
Garrett,
531 U.S.
356, 365 (2001). The Reconstruction Amendments “forbi[d], so
far as civil and political rights are concerned, discrimination
. . . against any citizen because of his race,” ensuring
that “[a]ll citizens are equal before the law.”
Gibson v.
Mississippi,
162 U.S.
565, 591 (1896) (Harlan, J.). They dictate “that the Government
must treat citizens as individuals, not as simply components of a
racial, religious, sexual or national class.”
Miller, 515
U. S., at 911 (internal quotation marks omitted). These
principles are why the Constitution presumptively forbids
race-predominant districting, “even for remedial purposes.”
Shaw
I, 509 U. S., at 657.
These same principles foreclose a construction
of the Amendments that would entitle members of racial minorities,
qua racial minorities, to have their preferred candidates
win elections. Nor do the Amendments limit the rights of members of
a racial majority to support
their preferred
candidates—regardless of whether minorities prefer different
candidates and of whether “the majority, by virtue of its numerical
superiority,” regularly prevails.
Gingles, 478 U. S.,
at 48. Nor, finally, do the Amendments establish a norm of
proportional control of elected offices on the basis of race. See
Parents Involved, 551 U. S., at 730–731 (plurality
opinion);
Shaw I, 509 U. S., at 657. And these notions
are not merely
foreign to the Amendments. Rather, they are
radically inconsistent with the Amendments’ command that
government treat citizens as individuals and their “goal of a
political system in which race no longer matters.”
Ibid.
Those notions are, however, the values at the
heart of §2 as construed by the District Court and the majority. As
applied here, the statute effectively considers it a legal wrong by
the State if white Alabamians vote for candidates from one
political party at high enough rates, provided that black
Alabamians vote for candidates from the other party at a still
higher rate. And the statute remedies that wrong by requiring the
State to engage in race-based redistricting in the direction of
proportional control.
I am not certain that Congress’ enforcement
power could
ever justify a statute so at odds “ ‘with
the letter and spirit of the constitution.’ ”
Shelby
County, 570 U. S., at 555. If it could, it must be because
Congress “identified a history and pattern” of actual
constitutional violations that, for some reason, required
extraordinary prophylactic remedies.
Garrett, 531
U. S., at 368. But the legislative record of the 1982
amendments is devoid of any showing that might justify §2’s blunt
approximation of a “racial register for allocating representation
on the basis of race.”
Holder, 512 U. S., at 908
(opinion of Thomas, J.). To be sure, the Senate Judiciary Committee
Report that accompanied the 1982 amendment to the Voting Rights Act
“listed many examples of what the Committee
took to be
unconstitutional vote dilution.”
Brnovich, 594 U. S.,
at ___ (slip op., at 6) (emphasis added). But the Report also
showed the Committee’s fundamental lack of “concern with whether”
those examples reflected the “intentional” discrimination required
“to raise a constitutional issue.”
Allen, 589 U. S., at
___ (slip op., at 15). The Committee’s “principal reason” for
rejecting discriminatory purpose was simply that it preferred an
alternative legal standard; it thought
Mobile’s intent test
was “the wrong question,” and that courts should instead ask
whether a State’s election laws offered minorities “a fair
opportunity to participate” in the political process. S. Rep.
No. 97–417, p. 36.
As applied here, the amended §2 thus falls on
the wrong side of “the line between measures that remedy or prevent
unconstitutional actions and measures that make a substantive
change in the governing law.”
City of Boerne, 521
U. S., at 519. It replaces the constitutional right against
intentionally discriminatory districting with an amorphous
race-based right to a “fair” distribution of political power, a
“right” that cannot be implemented without requiring the very evils
the Constitution forbids.
If that alone were not fatal, §2’s “reach and
scope” further belie any congruence and proportionality between its
districting-related commands, on the one hand, and actionable
constitutional wrongs, on the other.
Id., at 532. Its
“[s]weeping coverage ensures its intrusion at every level of
government” and in every electoral system.
Ibid. It “has no
termination date or termination mechanism.”
Ibid. Thus, the
amended §2 is not spatially or temporally “limited to those cases
in which constitutional violations [are] most likely.”
Id.,
at 533. Nor does the statute limit its reach to “attac[k] a
particular type” of electoral mechanism “with a long history as a
‘notorious means to deny and abridge voting rights on racial
grounds.’ ”
Ibid. (quoting
South Carolina v.
Katzenbach,
383
U.S. 301, 355 (1966) (Black, J., concurring and dissenting)).
In view of this “indiscriminate scope,” “it simply cannot be said
that ‘many of [the districting plans] affected by the congressional
enactment have a significant likelihood of being
unconstitutional.’ ”
Florida Prepaid Postsecondary Ed.
Expense Bd. v.
College Savings Bank,
527 U.S.
627, 647 (1999) (quoting
City of Boerne, 521 U. S.,
at 532).
Of course, under the logically unbounded
totality-of-circumstances inquiry, a court applying §2 can always
embroider its vote-dilution determination with findings about past
or present unconstitutional discrimination. But this possibility
does nothing to heal either the fundamental contradictions between
§2 and the Constitution or its extreme overbreadth relative to
actual constitutional wrongs. “A generalized assertion of past
discrimination” cannot justify race-based redistricting, “because
it provides no guidance for a legislative body to determine the
precise scope of the injury it seeks to remedy.”
Shaw II,
517 U. S., at 909 (internal quotation marks omitted). To
justify a statute tending toward the proportional allocation of
political power by race throughout the Nation, it cannot be enough
that a court can recite some indefinite quantum of discrimination
in the relevant jurisdiction. If it were, courts “could uphold
[race-based] remedies that are ageless in their reach into the
past, and timeless in their ability to affect the future.”
Wygant v.
Jackson Bd. of Ed.,
476
U.S. 267, 276 (1986) (plurality opinion). That logic “would
effectively assure that race will always be relevant in
[redistricting], and that the ultimate goal of eliminating entirely
from governmental decisionmaking such irrelevant factors as a human
being’s race will never be achieved.”
Parents Involved, 551
U. S., at 730 (plurality opinion) (alteration and internal
quotation marks omitted).
For an example of these baleful results, we need
look no further than the congressional districts at issue here. In
1992, Alabama and a group of §2 plaintiffs, whom a federal court
chose to regard as the representatives “of all African-American
citizens of the State of Alabama,” stipulated that the State’s
black population was “ ‘sufficiently compact and contiguous to
comprise a single member significant majority (65% or more) African
American Congressional district,’ ” and that,
“ ‘[c]onsequently,’ ” such a “ ‘district should be
created.’ ”
Wesch v.
Hunt,
785
F. Supp. 1491, 1493, 1498 (SD Ala.). Accepting that
stipulation, the court reworked District 7 into an irregularly
shaped supermajority-black district—one that scooped up populous
clusters of black voters in the disparate urban centers of
Birmingham and Montgomery to connect them across a swath of largely
majority-black rural areas—without even “decid[ing] whether the
creation of a majority African-American district [was] mandated by
either §2 or the Constitution.”
Id., at 1499; see n. 7,
supra. It did not occur to the court that the Constitution
might
forbid such an extreme racial gerrymander, as it quite
obviously did. But, once District 7 had come into being as a racial
gerrymander thought necessary to satisfy §2, it became an
all-but-immovable fixture of Alabama’s districting scheme.
Now, 30 years later, the plaintiffs here demand
that Alabama carve up not two but three of its main urban centers
on the basis of race, and that it configure those urban centers’
black neighborhoods with the outlying majority-black rural areas so
that black voters can control not one but two of the State’s seven
districts. The Federal Judiciary now upholds their
demand—overriding the State’s undoubted interest in preserving the
core of its existing districts, its plainly reasonable desire to
maintain the Gulf Coast region as a cohesive political unit, and
its persuasive arguments that a race-neutral districting process
would not produce anything like the districts the plaintiffs seek.
Our reasons for doing so boil down to these: that the plaintiffs’
proposed districts are more or less within the vast universe of
reasonable districting outcomes; that Alabama’s white voters do not
support the black minority’s preferred candidates; that Alabama’s
racial climate, taken as a rarefied whole, crosses some indefinable
line justifying our interference; and, last but certainly not
least, that black Alabamians are about two-sevenths of the State’s
overall population.
By applying §2 in this way to claims of this
kind, we encourage a conception of politics as a struggle for power
between “competing racial factions.”
Shaw I, 509 U. S.,
at 657. We indulge the pernicious tendency of assigning Americans
to “creditor” and “debtor race[s],” even to the point of
redistributing political power on that basis.
Adarand
Constructors, Inc. v.
Peña,
515
U.S. 200, 239 (1995) (Scalia, J., concurring in part and
concurring in judgment). We ensure that the race-based
redistricting we impose on Alabama now will bear divisive
consequences long into the future, just as the initial creation of
District 7 segregated Jefferson County for decades and minted the
template for crafting black “political homelands” in Alabama.
Holder, 512 U. S., at 905 (opinion of Thomas, J.). We
place States in the impossible position of having to weigh just how
much racial sorting is necessary to avoid the “competing hazards”
of violating §2 and violating the Constitution.
Abbott, 585
U. S., at ___ (slip op., at 4) (internal quotation marks
omitted). We have even put ourselves in the ridiculous position of
“assuming” that compliance with a statute can excuse disobedience
to the Constitution. Worst of all, by making it clear that there
are political dividends to be gained in the discovery of new ways
to sort voters along racial lines, we prolong immeasurably the day
when the “sordid business” of “divvying us up by race” is no more.
LULAC, 548 U. S., at 511 (Roberts, C. J.,
concurring in part, concurring in judgment in part, and dissenting
in part). To the extent §2 requires any of this, it is
unconstitutional.
The majority deflects this conclusion by
appealing to two of our older Voting Rights Act cases,
City of
Rome v.
United States,
446 U.S.
156 (1980), and
South Carolina v.
Katzenbach,
383 U.S.
301, that did not address §2 at all and, indeed, predate
Congress’ adoption of the results test.
Ante, at 33–34. That
maneuver is untenable.
Katzenbach upheld §5’s preclearance
requirements, §4(b)’s original coverage formula, and other related
provisions aimed at “a small number of States and political
subdivisions” where “systematic resistance to the Fifteenth
Amendment” had long been flagrant. 383 U. S., at 328; see also
id., at 315–317 (describing the limited issues presented).
Fourteen years later,
City of Rome upheld the 1975 Act
extending §5’s preclearance provisions for another seven years. See
446 U. S., at 172–173. The majority’s reliance on these cases
to validate a statutory rule not there at issue could make sense
only if we assessed the congruence and proportionality of the
Voting Rights Act’s rules wholesale, without considering their
individual features, or if
Katzenbach and
City of
Rome meant that Congress has plenary power to enact whatever
rules it chooses to characterize as combating “discriminatory
. . . effect[s].”
Ante, at 33 (internal quotation
marks omitted). Neither proposition makes any conceptual sense or
is consistent with our cases. See,
e.g.,
Shelby
County, 570 U. S., at 550–557 (holding the 2006
preclearance coverage formula unconstitutional);
Northwest
Austin Municipal Util. Dist. No. One v.
Holder,
557 U.S.
193, 203 (2009) (emphasizing the distinctness of §§2 and 5);
City of Boerne, 521 U. S., at 533 (discussing
City
of Rome as a paradigm case of congruence-and-proportionality
review of remedial legislation);
Miller, 515 U. S., at
927 (stressing that construing §5 to require “that States engage in
presumptively unconstitutional race-based districting” would raise
“troubling and difficult constitutional questions,” notwithstanding
City of Rome).
In fact, the majority’s cases confirm the very
limits on Congress’ enforcement powers that are fatal to the
District Court’s construction of §2.
City of Rome, for
example, immediately after one of the sentences quoted by the
majority, explained the remedial rationale for its approval of the
1975 preclearance extension: “Congress could rationally have
concluded that, because electoral changes
by jurisdictions with
a demonstrable history of intentional racial discrimination in
voting create the risk of purposeful discrimination, it was
proper to prohibit changes that have a discriminatory impact.” 446
U. S., at 177 (emphasis added; footnote omitted). The next
section of
City of Rome then separately examined and upheld
the reasonableness of the extension’s 7-year time period. See
id., at 181–182.
City of Rome thus stands for
precisely the propositions for which
City of Boerne cited
it: Congress may adopt “[p]reventive measures . . . when
there is reason to believe that many of the laws affected by the
congressional enactment have a significant likelihood of being
unconstitutional,” 521 U. S., at 532, particularly when it
employs “termination dates, geographic restrictions, or egregious
predicates” that “tend to ensure Congress’ means are proportionate
to ends legitimate,”
id., at 533; see also
id., at
532–533 (analyzing
Katzenbach in similar terms);
Shelby
County, 570 U. S., at 535, 545–546 (same). Again, however,
the amended §2 lacks any such salutary limiting principles; it is
unbounded in time, place, and subject matter, and its
districting-related commands have no nexus to any likely
constitutional wrongs.
In short, as construed by the District Court, §2
does not remedy or deter unconstitutional discrimination in
districting in any way, shape, or form. On the contrary, it
requires it, hijacking the districting process to pursue a
goal that has no legitimate claim under our constitutional system:
the proportional allocation of political power on the basis of
race. Such a statute “cannot be considered remedial, preventive
legislation,” and the race-based redistricting it would command
cannot be upheld under the Constitution.
City of Boerne, 521
U. S., at 532.[
21]
IV
These cases are not close. The plaintiffs did
not prove that Alabama’s districting plan “impose[s] or applie[s]”
any “voting qualification or prerequisite to voting or standard,
practice, or procedure” that effects “a denial or abridgement of
the[ir] right . . . to vote on account of race or color.”
§10301(a). Nor did they prove that Alabama’s congressional
districts “are not equally open to participation” by black
Alabamians. §10301(b). The plaintiffs did not even prove that it is
possible to achieve two majority-black districts without resorting
to a racial gerrymander. The most that they can be said to have
shown is that sophisticated mapmakers can proportionally allocate
Alabama’s congressional districts based on race in a way that
exceeds the Federal Judiciary’s ability to recognize as a racial
gerrymander with the naked eye. The District Court held that this
showing, plus racially polarized voting and its
gestalt view
of Alabama’s racial climate, was enough to require the State to
redraw its districting plan on the basis of race. If that is the
benchmark for vote dilution under §2, then §2 is nothing more than
a racial entitlement to roughly proportional control of elective
offices—limited only by feasibility—wherever different racial
groups consistently prefer different candidates.
If that is what §2 means, the Court should hold
that it is unconstitutional. If that is not what it means, but §2
applies to districting, then the Court should hold that
vote-dilution challenges require a race-neutral benchmark that
bears no resemblance to unconstitutional racial registers. On the
other hand, if the Court believes that finding a race-neutral
benchmark is as impossible as much of its rhetoric suggests, it
should hold that §2 cannot be applied to single-member districting
plans for want of an “objective and workable standard for choosing
a reasonable benchmark.”
Holder, 512 U. S., at 881
(plurality opinion). Better yet, it could adopt the correct
interpretation of §2 and hold that a single-member districting plan
is not a “voting qualification,” a “prerequsite to voting,” or a
“standard, practice, or procedure,” as the Act uses those terms.
One way or another, the District Court should be reversed.
The majority goes to great lengths to decline
all of these options and, in doing so, to fossilize all of the
worst aspects of our long-deplorable vote-dilution jurisprudence.
The majority recites
Gingles’ shopworn phrases as if their
meaning were self-evident, and as if it were not common knowledge
that they have spawned intractable difficulties of definition and
application. It goes out of its way to reaffirm §2’s applicability
to single-member districting plans both as a purported original
matter and on highly exaggerated
stare decisis grounds. It
virtually ignores Alabama’s primary argument—that, whatever the
benchmark is, it must be race neutral—choosing, instead, to
quixotically joust with an imaginary adversary. In the process, it
uses special pleading to close the door on the hope cherished by
some thoughtful observers, see
Gonzalez, 535 F. 3d, at
599–600, that computational redistricting methods might offer a
principled, race-neutral way out of the thicket
Gingles
carried us into. Finally, it dismisses grave constitutional
questions with an insupportably broad holding based on demonstrably
inapposite cases.[
22]
I find it difficult to understand these
maneuvers except as proceeding from a perception that what the
District Court did here is essentially no different from what many
courts have done for decades under this Court’s superintendence,
joined with a sentiment that it would be unthinkable to disturb
that approach to the Voting Rights Act in any way. I share the
perception, but I cannot understand the sentiment. It is true that,
“under our direction, federal courts [have been] engaged in
methodically carving the country into racially designated electoral
districts” for decades now.
Holder, 512 U. S., at 945
(opinion of Thomas, J.). But that fact should inspire us to
repentance, not resignation. I am even more convinced of the
opinion that I formed 29 years ago:
“In my view, our current practice should
not continue. Not for another Term, not until the next case, not
for another day. The disastrous implications of the policies we
have adopted under the Act are too grave; the dissembling in our
approach to the Act too damaging to the credibility of the Federal
Judiciary. The ‘inherent tension’—indeed, I would call it an
irreconcilable conflict—between the standards we have adopted for
evaluating vote dilution claims and the text of the Voting Rights
Act would itself be sufficient in my view to warrant overruling the
interpretation of §2 set out in
Gingles. When that obvious
conflict is combined with the destructive effects our expansive
reading of the Act has had in involving the Federal Judiciary in
the project of dividing the Nation into racially segregated
electoral districts, I can see no reasonable alternative to
abandoning our current unfortunate understanding of the Act.”
Id., at 944.
I respectfully dissent.