NOTICE: This opinion is subject to
formal revision before publication in the preliminary print of the
United States Reports. Readers are requested to notify the
Reporter of Decisions, Supreme Court of the United States,
Washington, D. C. 20543, of any typographical or other formal
errors, in order that corrections may be made before the
preliminary print goes to press.
SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
_________________
No. 14–940
_________________
SUE EVENWEL, et al., APPELLANTS
v.
GREG ABBOTT, governor of texas, et al.
on appeal from the united states district
court for the western district of texas
[April 4, 2016]
Justice Ginsburg delivered the opinion of the
Court.
Texas, like all other States, draws its
legislative districts on the basis of total population.
Plaintiffs-appellants are Texas voters; they challenge this uniform
method of districting on the ground that it produces un-equal
districts when measured by voter-eligible population.Voter-eligible
population, not total population, they urge, must be used to ensure
that their votes will not be devalued in relation to
citizens’ votes in other districts. We hold, based on
constitutional history, this Court’s decisions, and
longstanding practice, that a State may draw its legislative
districts based on total population.
I
A
This Court long resisted any role in
overseeing the process by which States draw legislative districts.
“The remedy for unfairness in districting,” the Court
once held, “is to secure State legislatures that will
apportion prop-erly, or to invoke the ample powers of
Congress.”
Colegrovev.
Green, 328 U. S.
549, 556 (1946) . “Courts ought not to enter this political
thicket,” as Justice Frankfurter put it.
Ibid.
Judicial abstention left pervasive
malapportionment unchecked. In the opening half of the 20th
century, there was a massive population shift away from rural areas
and toward suburban and urban communities. Nevertheless, many
States ran elections into the early 1960’s based on maps
drawn to equalize each district’s population as it was
composed around 1900. Other States used maps allocating a certain
number of legislators to each county regardless of its population.
These schemes left many rural districts significantly
underpopulated in comparison with urban and suburban districts. But
rural legislators who benefited from malapportionment had scant
incentive to adopt new maps that might put them out of office.
The Court confronted this ingrained structural
inequal-ity in
Baker v.
Carr, 369 U. S. 186
–192 (1962). Thatcase presented an equal protection challenge
to a Tennessee state-legislative map that had not been redrawn
since 1901. See also
id., at 192 (observing that, in the
meantime, there had been “substantial growth and
redistribution” of the State’s population). Rather than
steering clear of the political thicket yet again, the Court held
for the first time that malapportionment claims are justiciable.
Id., at 237 (“We conclude that the complaint’s
allegations of a denial of equal protection present a justiciable
constitutional cause of action upon which appellants are entitled
to a trial and a decision.”).
Although the Court in
Baker did not reach
the merits of the equal protection claim,
Baker’s
justiciability ruling set the stage for what came to be known as
the one-person, one-vote principle. Just two years after
Baker, in
Wes-berry v.
Sanders, 376 U. S.
1 –8 (1964), the Court invalidated Georgia’s
malapportioned congressional map, underwhich the population of one
congressional district was “two to three times” larger
than the population of the others. Relying on Article I, §2,
of the Constitution, the Court required that congressional
districts be drawn with equal populations.
Id., at 7, 18.
Later that same Term, in
Reynolds v.
Sims, 377
U. S. 533, 568 (1964) , the Court upheld an equal protection
challenge to Alabama’s malapportioned state-legislative maps.
“[T]he Equal Protection Clause,” the Court concluded,
“requires that the seats in both houses of a bicameral state
legislature must be apportioned on a population basis.”
Ibid.
Wesberry and
Reynolds together
instructed that jurisdictions must design both congressional and
state-legislative districts with equal populations, and must
regularly reapportion districts to prevent
malapportionment.[
1]
Over the ensuing decades, the Court has several
times elaborated on the scope of the one-person, one-vote rule.
States must draw congressional districts with populations as close
to perfect equality as possible. See
Kirkpatrick v.
Preisler, 394 U. S. 526 –531 (1969). But, when
drawing state and local legislative districts, jurisdictions are
permitted to deviate somewhat from perfect population equality to
accommodate traditional districting objectives, among them
,
preserving the integrity of political subdivisions, maintaining
communities of interest, and creating geographic compactness. See
Brown v.
Thomson, 462 U. S. 835 –843
(1983). Where the maximum population deviation between the largest
and smallest district is less than 10%, the Court has held, a state
or local legislative map presumptively complies with the
one-person, one-vote rule.
Ibid.[
2] Maximum deviations above 10% are presumptively
impermissible.
Ibid. See also
Mahan v.
Howell,
410 U. S. 315, 329 (1973) (approving a state-legislative map
with maximum population deviation of 16% to accommodate the
State’s interest in “maintaining the integrity of
political subdivision lines,” but cautioning that this
deviation “may well approach tolerable limits”).
In contrast to repeated disputes over the
permissibility of deviating from perfect population equality,
little controversy has centered on the population base
jurisdictions must equalize. On rare occasions, jurisdictions have
relied on the registered-voter or voter-eligible populations of
districts. See
Burns v.
Richardson, 384 U. S. 73
–94 (1966) (holding Hawaii could use a registered-voter
population base because of “Hawaii’s special population
problems”—in particular, its substantial temporary
military population). But, in the overwhelming majority of cases,
jurisdictions have equalized total population, as measured by the
decennial census. Today, all States use total-population numbers
from the census when designing congressional and state-legislative
districts, and only seven States adjust those census numbers in any
meaningful way.[
3]
B
Appellants challenge that consensus. After the
2010 census, Texas redrew its State Senate districts using a
total-population baseline. At the time, Texas was subject to the
preclearance requirements of §5 of the Voting Rights Act of
1965. 52 U. S. C. §10304 (requiring jurisdictions to
receive approval from the U. S. Department of Justice or the
U. S. District Court for the District of Columbia before
implementing certain voting changes). Once it became clear that the
new Senate map, S148, would not receive preclearance in advance of
the 2012 elections, the U. S. District Court for the Western
District of Texas drew an interim Senate map, S164, which also
equalized the total population of each district. See
Davis
v.
Perry, No. SA–11–CV–788 (Nov. 23,
2011).[
4] On direct appeal,
this Court observed that the District Court had failed to
“take guidance from the State’s recently enacted plan
in drafting an interim plan,” and therefore vacated the
District Court’s map.
Perry v.
Perez, 565
U. S. ___, ___, ___–___ (2012) (
per curiam) (slip
op., at 4, 8–10).
The District Court, on remand, again used census
data to draw districts so that each included roughly the same size
total population. Texas used this new interim map, S172, in the
2012 elections, and, in 2013, the Texas Legislature adopted S172 as
the permanent Senate map. See App. to Brief for Texas Senate
Hispanic Caucus et al. as
Amici Curiae 5 (reproducing
the current Senate map). The permanent map’s maximum
total-population deviation is 8.04%, safely within the
presumptively permissible 10% range. But measured by a
voter-population baseline—eligible voters or registered
voters—the map’s maximum population deviation exceeds
40%.
Appellants Sue Evenwel and Edward Pfenninger
live in Texas Senate districts (one and four, respectively) with
particularly large eligible- and registered-voter populations.
Contending that basing apportionment on total population dilutes
their votes in relation to voters in other Senate districts, in
violation of the one-person, one-vote principle of the Equal
Protection Clause,[
5]
appellants filed suit in the U. S. District Court for the
Western District of Texas. They named as defendants the Governor
and Secretary of State of Texas, and sought a permanent injunction
barring use of the existing Senate map in favor of a map that would
equalize the voter population in each district.
The case was referred to a three-judge District
Court for hearing and decision. See 28 U. S. C.
§2284(a);
Shapiro v.
McManus, 577 U. S.
___, ___–___ (2015) (slip op., at 5–7). That court
dismissed the complaint for failure to state a claim on which
relief could be granted. Appellants, the District Court explained,
“rel[y] upon a theory never before accepted by the Supreme
Court or any circuit court: that the metric of apportionment
employed by Texas (total population) results in an unconstitutional
apportionment because it does not achieve equality as measured by
Plaintiffs’ chosen metric—voter population.” App.
to Juris. Statement 9a. Decisions of this Court, the District Court
concluded, permit jurisdictions to use any neutral,
nondiscriminatory population baseline, including total population,
when drawing state and local legislative districts.
Id., at
13a–14a.[
6]
We noted probable jurisdiction, 575 U. S.
___ (2015), and now affirm.
II
The parties and the United States advance
different positions in this case. As they did before the District
Court, appellants insist that the Equal Protection Clause requires
jurisdictions to draw state and local legislative districts with
equal voter-eligible populations, thus protecting “voter
equality,”
i.e., “the right of eligible voters
to an equal vote.” Brief for Appellants 14.[
7] To comply with their proposed rule,
appellants suggest, jurisdictions should design districts based on
citizen-voting-age-population (CVAP) data from the Census
Bureau’s American Community Survey (ACS), an annual
statistical sample of the U. S. population. Texas responds
that jurisdic-tions may, consistent with the Equal Protection
Clause, design districts using any population
baseline—including total population and voter-eligible
population—so long as the choice is rational and not
invidiously discriminatory. Although its use of total-population
data from the census was permissible, Texas therefore argues, it
could have used ACS CVAP data instead. Sharing Texas’
position that the Equal Protection Clause does not mandate use of
voter-eligible population, the United States urges us not to
address Texas’ separate assertion that the Constitution
allows States to use alternative population baselines, including
voter-eligible population. Equalizing total population, the United
States maintains, vindicates the principle of representational
equality by “ensur[ing] that the voters in each district have
the power to elect a representative who represents the same number
of constituents as all other representatives.” Brief for
United States as
Amicus Curiae 5.
In agreement with Texas and the United States,
we reject appellants’ attempt to locate a voter-equality
mandate in the Equal Protection Clause. As history, precedent, and
practice demonstrate, it is plainly permissible for jurisdictions
to measure equalization by the total population of state and local
legislative districts.
A
We begin with constitutional history. At the
time of the founding, the Framers confronted a question analogous
to the one at issue here: On what basis should congressional
districts be allocated to States? The Framers’ solution, now
known as the Great Compromise, was to provide each State the same
number of seats in the Senate, and to allocate House seats based on
States’ total populations. “Representatives and direct
Taxes,” they wrote, “shall be apportioned among the
several States which may be included within this Union,
according to their respective Numbers.” U. S.
Const., Art. I, §2, cl. 3 (emphasis added). “It is
a fundamental principle of the proposed constitution,” James
Madison explained in the Federalist Papers, “that as the
aggregate number of representatives allotted to the several states,
is to be . . . founded on the aggregate number of
inhabitants; so, the right of choosing this allotted number in each
state, is to be exercised by such part of the inhabitants, as the
state itself may designate.” The Federalist No. 54, p. 284
(G. Carey & J. McClellan eds. 2001). In other words, the basis
of
representation in the House was to include all
inhabitants—although slaves were counted as only three-fifths
of a person—even though States remained free to deny many of
those inhabitants the right to participate in the selection of
their representatives.[
8]
Endorsing apportionment based on total population, Alexander
Hamilton declared: “There can be no truer principle than
this—that every individual of the commu-nity at large has an
equal right to the protection of govern-ment.” 1 Records of
the Federal Convention of 1787, p. 473 (M. Farrand ed.
1911).[
9]
When debating what is now the Fourteenth
Amendment, Congress reconsidered the proper basis for apportioning
House seats. Concerned that Southern States would not willingly
enfranchise freed slaves, and aware that “a slave’s
freedom could swell his state’s population for purposes of
representation in the House by one person, rather than only
three-fifths,” the Framers of the Fourteenth Amendment
considered at length the possibility of allocating House seats to
States on the basis of voter population. J. Sneed, Footprints on
the Rocks of the Mountain: An Account of the Enactment of the
Fourteenth Amendment 28 (1997). See also
id., at 35
(“[T]he apportionment issue consumed more time in the
Fourteenth Amendment debates than did any other topic.”).
In December 1865, Thaddeus Stevens, a leader of
the Radical Republicans, introduced a constitutional amendment that
would have allocated House seats to States “according to
their respective legal voters”; in addition, the proposed
amendment mandated that “[a] true census of the legal voters
shall be taken at the same time with the regular census.”
Cong. Globe, 39th Cong., 1st Sess., 10 (1866). Supporters of
apportionment based on voter population employed the same
voter-equality reasoning that appellants now echo. See,
e.g., id., at 380 (remarks of Rep. Orth)
(“[T]he true principle of representation in Congress is that
voters alone should form the basis, and that each voter should have
equal political weight in our
Government. . . .”);
id., at 404
(remarks of Rep. Lawrence) (use of total population
“disregards the fundamental idea of all just representation,
that every voter should be equal in political power all over the
Union”).
Voter-based apportionment proponents encountered
fierce resistance from proponents of total-population
apportionment. Much of the opposition was grounded in the principle
of representational equality. “As an abstract
proposition,” argued Representative James G. Blaine, a
leading critic of allocating House seats based on voter population,
“no one will deny that population is the true basis of
representation; for women, children, and other non-voting classes
may have as vital an interest in the legislation of the country as
those who actually deposit the ballot.”
Id., at 141.
See also
id., at 358 (remarks of Rep. Conkling) (arguing
that use of a voter-population basis “would shut out four
fifths of the citizens of the country—women and children, who
are citizens, who are taxed, and who are, and always have been,
represented”);
id., at 434 (remarks of Rep. Ward)
(“[W]hat becomes of that large class of non-voting tax-payers
that are found in every section? Are they in no matter to be
represented? They certainly should be enumerated in making up the
whole number of those entitled to a representative.”).
The product of these debates was §2 of the
Fourteenth Amendment, which retained total population as the
congressional apportionment base. See U. S. Const., Amdt. 14,
§2 (“Representatives shall be apportioned among the
several States according to their respective numbers, counting the
whole number of persons in each State, excluding Indians not
taxed.”). Introducing the final version of the Amendment on
the Senate floor, Senator Jacob Howard explained:
“[The] basis of representation is
numbers . . . ; that is, the whole population except
untaxed Indians and persons excluded by the State laws for
rebellion or other crime. . . . The committee
adopted numbers as the most just and satisfactory basis, and this
is the principle upon which the Constitution itself was originally
framed, that the basis of representation should depend upon
numbers; and such, I think, after all, is the safest and most
secure principle upon which the Government can rest. Numbers, not
voters; numbers, not property; this is the theory of the
Constitution.” Cong. Globe, 39th Cong., 1st Sess.,
2766–2767 (1866).
Appellants ask us to find in the Fourteenth
Amendment’s Equal Protection Clause a rule inconsistent with
this “theory of the Constitution.” But, as the Court
recognized in
Wesberry, this theory underlies not just the
method of allocating House seats to States; it applies as well
tothe method of apportioning legislative seats within States.
“The debates at the [Constitutional] Convention,” the
Court explained, “make at least one fact abundantly clear:
that when the delegates agreed that the House should represent
‘people,’ they intended that in allocating Congressmen
the number assigned to each state should be determined solely by
the number of inhabitants.” 376 U. S., at 13.
“While it may not be possible to draw congressional districts
with mathematical precision,” the Court acknowledged,
“that is no excuse for ignoring our Constitution’s
plain objective of making equal representation for
equal numbers
of people the fundamental goalfor the House of
Representatives.”
Id., at 18 (emphasis added). It
cannot be that the Fourteenth Amendment calls for the apportionment
of congressional districts based on total population, but
simultaneously prohibits States from apportioning their own
legislative districts on the same basis.
Cordoning off the constitutional history of
congressional districting, appellants stress two points.[
10] First, they draw a distinction
between allocating seats
to States, and apportioning seats
within States. The Framers selected total population for the
former, appellants and their
amici argue, because of
federalism concerns inapposite to intra-state districting. These
concerns included the perceived risk that a voter-population base
might encourage States to expand the franchise unwisely, and the
hope that a total-population base might counter States’
incentive to undercount their populations, thereby reducing their
share of direct taxes.
Wesberry, however, rejected the
distinction appellants now press. See
supra, at 12. Even
without the weight of
Wesberry, we would find
appellants’ distinction unconvincing. One can accept that
federalism—or, as Justice Alito emphasizes, partisan and
regional political advantage, see
post, at
6–13—figured in the Framers’ selection of total
population as the basis for allocating congressional seats. Even
so, it remains beyond doubt that the principle of representational
equality figured prominently in the decision to count people,
whether or not they qualify as voters.[
11]
Second, appellants and Justice Alito urge, see
post, at 5–6, the Court has typically refused to
analogize to features of the federal electoral system—here,
the constitutional scheme governing congressional
apportionment—when considering challenges to state and local
election laws. True, in
Reynolds, the Court rejected
Alabama’s argument that it had permissibly modeled its State
Senate apportionment scheme—one Senator for each
county—on the United States Senate. “[T]he federal
analogy,” the Court explained, “[is] inapposite and
irrelevant to state legislative districting schemes” because
“[t]he system of representation in the two Houses of the
Federal Congress” arose “from unique historical
circumstances.” 377 U. S., at 573–574. Likewise,
in
Gray v.
Sanders, 372 U. S. 368 –372,
378 (1963), Georgia unsuccessfully attempted to defend, by analogy
to the electoral college, its scheme of assigning a certain number
of “units” to the winner of each county in statewide
elections.
Reynolds and
Gray, however,
involved features of the federal electoral system that contravene
the principles of both voter
and representational equality
to favor interests that have no relevance outside the federal
context. Senate seats were allocated to States on an equal basis to
respect state sovereignty and increase the odds that the smaller
States would ratify the Constitution. See
Wesberry, 376
U. S., at 9–13 (describing the history of the Great
Compromise). See also
Reynolds, 377 U. S., at 575
(“Political subdivisions of States—counties, cities, or
whatever—never were and never have been considered as
sovereign entities. . . . The relationship of the
States to the Federal Government could hardly be less
analogous.”). “The [Electoral] College was created to
permit the most knowledge-able members of the community to choose
the executive of anation whose continental dimensions were thought
to preclude an informed choice by the citizenry at large.”
Williams v.
Rhodes, 393 U. S. 23 –44
(1968) (Harlan, J., concurring in result). See also
Gray,
372 U. S., at 378 (“The inclusion of the electoral
college in the Constitution, as the result of specific historical
concerns, validated the collegiate principle despite its inherent
numerical inequality.” (footnote omitted)). By contrast, as
earlier developed, the constitutional scheme for congressional
apportion-ment rests in part on the same representational concerns
that exist regarding state and local legislative districting. The
Framers’ answer to the apportionment question inthe
congressional context therefore undermines appellants’
contention that districts must be based on voter population.
B
Consistent with constitutional history, this
Court’s past decisions reinforce the conclusion that States
and localities may comply with the one-person, one-vote principle
by designing districts with equal total populations. Quoting
language from those decisions that, in appellants’ view,
supports the principle of equal voting power—and emphasizing
the phrase “one-person, one-vote”—appellants
contend that the Court had in mind, and constantly meant, that
States should equalize the voter-eligible population of districts.
See
Reynolds, 377 U. S., at 568 (“[A]n
individual’s right to vote for State legislators is
unconstitutionally impaired when its weight is in a substantial
fashion diluted when compared with votes of citizens living on
other parts of the State.”);
Gray, 372 U. S., at
379–380 (“The concept of ‘we the people’
under the Constitution visualizes no preferred class of voters but
equality among those who meet the basic qualifications.”).
See also
Hadley v.
Junior College Dist. of Metropolitan
Kansas City, 397 U. S. 50, 56 (1970) (“[W]hen
members of an elected body are chosen from separate districts, each
district must be established on a basis that will insure, as far as
is practicable, that equal numbers of voters can vote for
proportionally equal numbers of officials.”). Appellants,
however, extract far too much from selectively chosen language and
the “one-person, one-vote” slogan.
For every sentence appellants quote from the
Court’s opinions, one could respond with a line casting the
one-person, one-vote guarantee in terms of equality of
representation, not voter equality. In
Reynolds, for
instance, the Court described “the fundamental principle of
representative government in this country” as “one of
equal representation for equal numbers of people.” 377
U. S., at 560–561. See also
Davis v.
Bandemer, 478 U. S. 109, 123 (1986) (“[I]n
formulating the one person, one vote formula, the Court
characterized the question posed by election districts of disparate
size as an issue of fair representation.”);
Reynolds,
377 U. S., at 563 (rejecting state districting schemes that
“give the same number of representatives to unequal numbers
of constituents”). And the Court has suggested, repeatedly,
that districting based on total population serves
both the
State’s interest in preventing vote dilution
and its
interest in ensuring equality of representation. See
Board of
Estimate of City of New York v.
Morris, 489 U. S.
688 –694 (1989) (“If districts of widely unequal
population elect an equal number of representatives, the voting
power of each citizen in the larger constituencies is debased and
the citizens in those districts have a smaller share of
representation than do those in the smaller districts.”). See
also
Kirkpatrick, 394 U. S., at 531 (recognizing in a
congressional-districting case that “[e]qual representation
for equal numbers of people is a principle designed to prevent
debasement of voting power and diminution of access to elected
representatives”).[
12]
Moreover, from
Reynolds on, the Court has
consistently looked to total-population figures when evaluating
whether districting maps violate the Equal Protection Clause
bydeviating impermissibly from perfect population equality. See
Brief for Appellees 29–31 (collecting cases brought under the
Equal Protection Clause). See also
id., at 31, n. 9
(collecting congressional-districting cases). Appellants point to
no instance in which the Court has determined the permissibility of
deviation based on eligible- or registered-voter data. It would
hardly make sense for the Court to have mandated voter equality
sub silentio and then used a total-population baseline to
evaluate compliance with that rule. More likely, we think, the
Court has always assumed the permissibility of drawing districts to
equalize total population.
“In the 1960s,” appellants counter,
“the distribution of the voting population generally did not
deviate from the distribution of total population to the degree
necessary to raise this issue.” Brief for Appellants 27. To
support this assertion, appellants cite only a District Court
decision, which found no significant deviation in the distribution
of voter and total population in “densely populated areas of
New York State.”
WMCA, Inc. v.
Lomenzo, 238
F. Supp. 916, 925 (SDNY), aff’d, 382 U. S. 4 (1965)
(
per curiam). Had this Court assumed such equivalence
on a national scale, it likely would have said as much.[
13] Instead, in
Gaffney v.
Cummings, 412 U. S. 735 –747 (1973), the Court
acknowledged that voters may be distributed un-evenly within
jurisdictions. “[I]f it is the weight of a person’s
vote that matters,” the Court observed, then “total
population—even if stable and accurately taken—may not
actually reflect that body of voters whose votes must be counted
and weighed for the purposes of reapportionment, because
‘census persons’ are not voters.”
Id., at
746. Nonetheless, the Court in
Gaffney recognized that the
one-person, one-vote rule is designed to facilitate
“[f ]air and effective representation,”
id., at 748, and evaluated compliance with the rule based on
total population alone,
id., at 750.
C
What constitutional history and our prior
decisions strongly suggest, settled practice confirms. Adopting
voter-eligible apportionment as constitutional command would upset
a well-functioning approach to districting that all 50 States and
countless local jurisdictions have followed for decades, even
centuries. Appellants have shown no reason for the Court to disturb
this longstanding use of total population. See
Walz v.
Tax Comm’n of City of New York, 397 U. S. 664,
678 (1970) (“unbroken practice” followed “openly
and by affirmative state action, not covertly or by state inaction,
is not something to be lightly cast aside”). See also
Burson v.
Freeman, 504 U. S. 191 –206
(1992) (plurality opinion) (upholding a law limiting campaigning in
areas around polling places in part because all 50 States maintain
such laws, so there is a “widespread and time-tested
consensus” that legislation of this order serves important
state interests). As the Framers of the Constitution and the
Fourteenth Amendment comprehended, representatives serve all
residents, not just those eligible or registered to vote. See
supra, at 8–12. Nonvoters have an important stake in
many policy debates—children, their parents, even their
grandparents, for example, have a stake in a strong
public-education system—and in receiving constituent
services, such as help navigating public-benefits bureaucracies. By
ensuring that each representative is subject to requests and
suggestions from the same number of constituents, total-population
apportionment promotes equitable and effective representation. See
McCormick v.
United States, 500 U. S. 257, 272
(1991) (“Serving constituents and supporting legislation that
will benefit the district and individ-uals and groups therein is
the everyday business of a legislator.”).[
14]
In sum, the rule appellants urge has no mooring
in the Equal Protection Clause. The Texas Senate map, we therefore
conclude, complies with the requirements of the one-person,
one-vote principle.[
15]
Because history, precedent, and practice suffice to reveal the
infirmity of appellants’ claims, we need not and do not
resolve whether, as Texas now argues, States may draw districts to
equalize voter-eligible population rather than total
population.
* * *
For the reasons stated, the judgment of the
United States District Court for the Western District of Texas
is
Affirmed.