NOTICE: This opinion is subject to formal revision before
publication in the preliminary print of the United States
Reports. Readers are requested to notify the Reporter of Decisions,
Supreme Court of the United States, Washington, D. C. 20543,
of any typographical or other formal errors, in order that
corrections may be made before the preliminary print goes to
press.
SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
_________________
No. 13–7211
_________________
ROBERT MITCHELL JENNINGS, PETITIONER v. WILLIAM STEPHENS,
DIRECTOR, TEXAS DE-PARTMENT OF CRIMINAL JUSTICE, COR-RECTIONAL
INSTITUTIONS DIVISION
on writ of certiorari to the united states court of appeals for
the fifth circuit
[January 14, 2015]
Justice Scalia delivered the opinion of the Court.
Petitioner Robert Mitchell Jennings was sentenced to death for
capital murder. He applied for federal habeas corpus relief on
three theories of ineffective assistance of counsel, prevailing on
two. The State appealed, and Jennings defended his writ on all
three theories. We consider whether Jennings was permitted to
pursue the theory that the District Court had rejected without
taking a cross-appeal or obtaining a certificate of
appealability.
I
In July 1988, petitioner Robert Mitchell Jennings entered an
adult bookstore to commit a robbery. Officer Elston Howard, by
unhappy coincidence, was at the same establishment to arrest the
store’s clerk. Undeterred, Jennings shot Howard four times, robbed
the store, and escaped. Howard died from his wounds.
Howard was merely the most recent victim of Jennings’
criminality. The State adjudicated Jennings a delinquent at 14,
convicted him of aggravated robbery at 17, and of additional
aggravated robberies at 20. He murdered Officer Howard only two
months after his most recent release from prison.
Jennings was arrested, tried, and convicted of capital murder,
and the State sought the death penalty. During the punishment
phase, the State introduced evidence of Jennings’ lengthy and
violent criminal history. Jennings’ attorney called only the prison
chaplain, who testified about Jennings’ improvement and that
Jennings was not “incorrigible.” Jennings’ attorney acknowledged
the difficulty of his sentencing defense in his closing remarks,
commenting that he could not “quarrel with” a death sentence, but
was nonetheless pleading for mercy for his client. The jury
returned a special verdict, consistent with Texas law, that
Jennings acted deliberately in the murder and that he would present
a continuing threat to society. The trial court sentenced Jennings
to death. Texas courts affirmed Jennings’ conviction and sentence
and denied postconviction relief. Jennings v. State,
No. AP–70911 (Tex. Crim. App., Jan. 20, 1993); Ex parte
Jennings, 2008 WL 5049911 (Tex. Crim. App., Nov. 26, 2008).
Jennings applied for federal habeas corpus relief, asserting, as
relevant here, three theories of ineffective assistance of counsel
in the punishment phase of his trial. Jennings first claimed trial
counsel was ineffective for failing to present evidence of his
disadvantaged background, including that his conception was the
product of his mother’s rape, that his mother was only 17 when he
was born, and that he grew up in poverty. Jennings offered his
mother and sister as witnesses.
Jennings next argued that trial counsel was ineffective for
failure to investigate and to present evidence of Jennings’ low
intelligence and organic brain damage. His trial attorney admitted
in affidavit that he failed to review the case files from Jennings’
prior convictions, which contained a report suggesting Jennings
suffered from mild mental retardation and mild organic brain
dysfunction. (The report also suggested that Jennings malingered,
feigning mental illness in order to delay proceedings.) Jennings
argued that trial counsel should have examined Jennings’ prior case
files, investigated Jennings’ mental health problems, and presented
evidence of mental impairment in the punishment phase.
Finally, Jennings argued that counsel was constitutionally
ineffective for stating that he could not “quarrel with” a death
sentence. According to Jennings, this remark expressed resignation
to—even the propriety of—a death sentence.
Jennings cited our decision in Wiggins v.
Smith,539 U. S. 510 (2003), as establishing constitutional
ineffectiveness when counsel fails to investigate or to introduce
substantial mitigating evidence in a sentencing proceeding. Though
he did not cite our decision in Smith v. Spisak,558
U. S. 139 (2010), he also argued that counsel’s closing
remarks amounted to constitutional ineffectiveness. The parties
referred to these alleged errors as the “Wiggins errors” and
the “Spisak error ”; we use the same terminology.
The federal habeas court granted Jennings relief on both of his
Wiggins theories, but denied relief on his Spisak
theory. Jennings v. Thaler, 2012 WL 1440387 (SD Tex.,
Apr. 23, 2012). The court ordered that the State “shall release
Jennings from custody unless, within 120 days, the State of Texas
grants Jennings a new sentencing hearing or resentences him to a
term of imprisonment as provided by Texas law at the time of
Jennings[ ’ ] crime.” Id., at *7.
The State appealed, attacking both Wiggins theories
(viz., trial counsel’s failure to present evidence of a deprived
background and failure to investigate evidence of mental
impairment). Jennings argued before the Fifth Circuit that the
District Court correctly found constitutional ineffectiveness on
both Wiggins theories, and argued again that trial counsel
performed ineffectively under his Spisak theory. The Fifth
Circuit reversed the grant of habeas corpus under the two
Wiggins theories and rendered judgment for the State. 537
Fed. Appx. 326, 334–335 (2013). The court determined that it lacked
jurisdiction over Jennings’ Spisak theory. Id., at
338–339. Implicitly concluding that raising this argument required
taking a cross-appeal, the panel noted that Jennings failed to file
a timely notice of appeal, see Fed. Rule App. Proc. 4(a)(1)(A), and
failed to obtain a certificate of appealability as required by28
U. S. C. §2253(c). Section 2253(c) provides, as relevant
here, that “[u]nless a circuit justice or judge issues a
certificate of appealability, an appeal may not be taken to the
court of appeals from . . . the final order in a habeas
corpus proceeding.”
We granted certiorari, 572 U. S. ___, (2014), to decide
whether Jennings was required to file a notice of cross-appeal and
seek a certificate of appealability to pursue his Spisak
theory.
II
The rules governing the argumentation permissible for appellees
urging the affirmance of judgment are familiar, though this case
shows that familiarity and clarity do not go hand-in-hand.
A
An appellee who does not take a cross-appeal may “urge in
support of a decree any matter appearing before the record,
although his argument may involve an attack upon the reasoning of
the lower court.” United States v. American Railway
Express Co.,265 U. S. 425,435 (1924). But an appellee who
does not cross-appeal may not “attack the decree with a view either
to enlarging his own rights thereunder or of lessening the rights
of his adversary.” Ibid. Since Jennings did not cross-appeal
the denial of his Spisak theory, we must determine whether
urging that theory sought to enlarge his rights or lessen the
State’s under the District Court’s judgment granting habeas
relief.
The District Court’s opinion, in its section labeled “Order,”
commanded the State to “release Jennings from custody unless,
within 120 days, the State of Texas grants Jennings a new
sentencing hearing or resentences him to a term of imprisonment as
provided by Texas law at the time of Jennings[ ’ ]
crime.” 2012 WL 1440387, at *7. The District Court’s corresponding
entry of judgment contained similar language. App. 35. The
intuitive answer to the question whether Jennings’ new theory
expands these rights is straightforward: Jennings’ rights under the
judgment were what the judgment provided—release, resentencing, or
commutation within a fixed time, at the State’s option; the
Spisak theory would give him the same. Similarly, the
State’s rights under the judgment were to retain Jennings in
custody pending resentencing or to commute his sentence; the
Spisak theory would allow no less.
The State objects to this straightforward result. A conditional
writ of habeas corpus, it argues, does not merely entitle a
successful petitioner to retrial (or resentencing), but it entitles
him to retrial (or resentencing) without the challenged
errors. Because each basis for habeas relief imposes an
additional implied obligation on the State (not to repeat
that error), each basis asserted by a successful petitioner
seeks to lessen the State’s rights at retrial, and therefore each
additional basis requires a cross-appeal.
This is an unusual position, and one contrary to the manner in
which courts ordinarily behave. Courts reduce their opinions and
verdicts to judgments precisely to define the rights and
liabilities of the parties. Parties seeking to enforce a foreign
court’s decree do not attempt to domesticate an opinion; they
domesticate a judgment. Restatement (Third) of Foreign
Relations Law of the United States §§ 481–482 (1987). A prevailing
party seeks to enforce not a district court’s reasoning, but the
court’s judgment. Rogers v. Hill,289
U. S. 582,587 (1933). This Court, like all federal appellate
courts, does not review lower courts’ opinions, but their
judgments. Chevron, U. S. A., Inc. v.
Natural Resources Defense Council, Inc.,467 U. S. 837,842
(1984). And so a rule that contravenes this structure, that makes
the opinion part of the judgment, is peculiar—especially when it is
applied to impose extrajudgment obligations on a sovereign
State.
The State’s argument might have force in a case where a district
court explicitly imposes (or the appellee asks the appellate
court explicitly to impose) a condition governing the details of
the retrial. But that case is not before us. The implications of
the State’s position make clear why such orders are atypical, and
why we should not infer such conditions from silence. Construing
every federal grant of habeas corpus as carrying an attendant list
of unstated acts (or omissions) that the state court must perform
(or not perform) would substantially transform conditional habeas
corpus relief from an opportunity “to replace an invalid judgment
with a valid one,” Wilkinson v. Dotson,544 U. S.
74 (Scalia, J., concurring), to a general grant of supervisory
authority over state trial courts.
In a variation on the same theme, the dissent posits that, apart
from implied terms, a habeas petitioner who successfully defends a
judgment on an alternative ground has expanded his rights
under the judgment, because he has changed the judgment’s
issue-preclusive effects. This theory confuses a party’s rights
under a judgment—here, the right to release, resentencing, or
commutation, at the State’s option—with preclusive effects that the
judgment might have in future proceedings. That makes nonsense of
American Railway. Whenever an appellee successfully
defends a judgment on an alternative ground, he changes what would
otherwise be the judgment’s issue-preclusive effects. Thereafter,
issue preclusion no longer attaches to the ground on which the
trial court decided the case, and instead attaches to the
alternative ground on which the appellate court affirmed the
judgment. Restatement (Second) of Judgments § 27 (1982). Thus,
making alteration of issue-preclusive effects the touchstone of
necessity for cross-appeal would require cross-appeal for
every defense of a judgment on alternative grounds. That is,
of course, the polar opposite of the rule we established in
American Railway.
Under the habeas court’s judgment, Jennings was entitled, at the
State’s option, to either release, resentencing, or commutation of
his sentence. Any potential claim that would have entitled Jennings
to a new sentencing proceeding could have been advanced to “urge
. . . support” of the judgment within the meaning of
American Railway. 265 U. S., at 435. The dissent and
the State contend that applying American Railway in this
fashion will lead to a proliferation of frivolous appellate
defenses in habeas cases. If so, that is a problem that can only be
solved by Congress. Until it does so, we think it appropriate to
adhere to the usual law of appeals.
We think, however, that the danger is exaggerated. To begin
with, not all defenses will qualify. A habeas applicant who has won
resentencing would be required to take a cross-appeal in order to
raise a rejected claim that would result in a new trial. Similarly,
even if a habeas applicant has won retrial below, a claim that his
conduct was constitutionally beyond the power of the State to
punish would require cross-appeal. And even a successful applicant
doing no more than defending his judgment on appeal is confined to
those alternative grounds present in the record: he may not
simply argue any alternative basis, regardless of its
origin. Ibid.
Moreover, successful habeas applicants have an incentive to
defend their habeas grants effectively, an objective that is not
furthered by diverting an appellate court’s attention from a
meritorious defense to a frivolous one. The dissent gives two
examples of habeas petitioners who raised numerous ostensibly
frivolous claims. Post, at 9. They prove nothing except the
dissent’s inability to substantiate its claim that our holding will
foster the presentation of frivolous alternative grounds for
affirmance. For both examples involved habeas petitioners who
lost before the magistrate and were casting about for any
basis that might justify a writ. We are talking here about habeas
petitioners who have won before the district court. The
notion that they can often be expected to dilute their defense of
the (by-definition-nonfrivolous) basis for their victory by
dragging in frivolous alternative grounds to support it is
thoroughly implausible. Indeed, as the State and Jennings agree, it
is rare that a habeas petitioner successful in the district court
will even be called upon to defend his writ on appeal.
And finally, we doubt that any more judicial time will be wasted
in rejection of frivolous claims made in defense of judgment on an
appeal already taken than would be wasted in rejection of similar
claims made in (what the State and dissent would require) a
separate proceeding for a certificate of appealability. To be sure,
as the dissent points out, post, at 9, the certificate
ruling will be made by just one judge rather than three; but that
judge will always be required to consider and rule on the
alternative grounds, whereas the three-judge court entertaining the
government’s habeas appeal will not reach the alternative grounds
unless it rejects the ground relied on by the lower court. Not to
mention the fact that in an already-pending appeal the court can
give the back of its hand to frivolous claims en passant,
whereas the certificate process requires the opening and
disposition of a separate proceeding.
In the end, the dissent tries to evade American Railway
by asserting that habeas corpus is “unique.” Post, at 7.
There are undoubtedly some differences between writs of habeas
corpus and other judgments—most notably, that habeas proceedings
traditionally ignored the claim-preclusive effect of earlier
adjudications. But the realitythat some things about habeas
are different does not mean that everything about habeas is
different. The dissent must justify why the particular distinction
it urges here—abandonment of the usual American Railway
rule—is an appropriate one. It cannot.
B
The State also advances what could be termed a corollary to the
American Railway rule. Citing Helvering v.
Pfeiffer,302 U. S. 247 (1937), and Alexander v.
Cosden Pipe Line Co.,290 U. S. 484 (1934), the State
insists that a cross-appeal is necessary not only for Jennings to
enlarge his rights under the District Court’s judgment, but also to
attack the District Court’s ruling rejecting his Spisak
theory, even if Jennings’ rights under the court’s judgment would
remain undisturbed.
The view of Pfeiffer and Alexander advanced by the
State would put these cases in considerable tension with our
oft-reaffirmed holding in American Railway. And it is not
the correct view. Both Pfeiffer and Alexander arose
from disputes between the Commissioner of the Internal Revenue
Service and taxpayers regarding multiple discrete federal tax
liabilities. Pfeiffer, supra, at 248;
Alexander, supra, at 486. In Pfeiffer, the
Commissioner prevailed before the Board of Tax Appeals on his
contention that a dividend was taxable, but lost a similar claim
against a cash payment. Only the taxpayer sought the Second
Circuit’s review, and the taxpayer prevailed on the dividend
liability. 302 U. S., at 249. In Alexander, the
taxpayer sought refund of four tax liabilities; the taxpayer won on
all four. Only the Commissioner appealed to the Tenth Circuit, and
that court affirmed two of the refunds, eliminated a third, and
reduced a fourth. Pfeiffer, supra, at 248–249;
Alexander, supra, at 486. The Commissioner sought our
review in both cases; we refused to entertain the Commissioner’s
arguments regarding the cash payment in Pfeiffer, or the
taxpayer’s regarding the elimi-nated and reduced claims in
Alexander, citing American Railway.
The State argues that these holdings expanded the need for
cross-appeal, beyond merely those arguments that would enlarge
rights under the judgment, to those arguments that revisit a lower
court’s disposition of an issue on which a judgment rests. For, the
State argues, the re-jected arguments would not necessarily
have expandedthe Commissioner’s or the taxpayer’s rights; if some
of the points on which the respective appellee won below were
rejected on appeal, his new arguments might do no more than
preserve the amount assessed.
But this view of Pfeiffer and Alexander distorts
American Railway. American Railway does not merely
require a cross-appeal where a party, if fully successful on his
new arguments, would certainly obtain greater relief than provided
below; it requires cross-appeal if the party’s arguments are
presented “with a view either to enlarging his own rights
thereunder or of lessening the rights of his adversary.” 265
U. S., at 435. In Pfeiffer and Alexander the
assertion of additional tax liabilities or defenses, respectively,
necessarily sought to enlarge or to reduce the Commissioner’s
rights, even if, under some combination of issues affirmed and
reversed, one possibility would have produced no more than the same
tax obligations pronounced by the judgment below.
Once we have rejected the State’s—and dissent’s—theories of
implied terms in conditional writs, Jennings’ Spisak theory
sought the same relief awarded under his Wiggins theories: a
new sentencing hearing. Whether prevailing on a single theory or
all three, Jennings sought the same, indivisible relief. This
occurred in neither Pfeiffer nor Alexander, and we
decline to view those cases as contradicting our ‘ “inveterate
and certain’ ” rule in American Railway.
Greenlaw v. United States,554 U. S. 237,245
(2008).
C
Finally, the State urges that even if Jennings was not required
to take a cross-appeal by American Railway, Pfeiffer,
and Alexander, he was required to obtain a certificate of
appealability. We disagree.
Section 2253(c) of Title 28 provides that “an appeal may not be
taken to the court of appeals” without a certificate of
appealability, which itself requires “a substantial showing of the
denial of a constitutional right.” It is unclear whether this
requirement applies to a habeas petitioner seeking to cross-appeal
in a case that is already before a court of appeals. Section
2253(c) performs an important gate-keeping function, but once a
State has properly noticed an appeal of the grant of habeas relief,
the court of appeals must hear the case, and “there are no
remaining gates to be guarded.” Szabo v. Walls, 313
F. 3d 392, 398 (CA7 2002) (Easterbrook, J.).
But we need not decide that question now, since it is clear that
§2253(c) applies only when “an appeal” is “taken to the court of
appeals.” Whether or not this embraces a cross-appeal, it assuredly
does not embrace the defense of a judgment on alternative grounds.
Congress enacted §2253(c) against the well-known, if not entirely
sharp, distinction between defending a judgment on appeal and
taking a cross-appeal. Nothing in the statute justifies ignoring
that distinction.
The dissent laments that this result frustrates AEDPA’s purpose
of preventing “frivolous appeals.” Post, at 8. It can
indulge that lament only by insisting that the defense of an
appealed judgment on alternative grounds is itself an appeal. The
two are not the same. The statutory text at issue here addresses
the “tak[ing]” of an appeal, not “the making of arguments in
defense of a judgment from which appeal has been taken.” Extending
the certificate of appealability requirement from the former to the
latter is beyond the power of the courts.
* * *
Because Jennings’ Spisak theory would neither have
enlarged his rights nor diminished the State’s rights under the
District Court’s judgment, he was required neither to take a
cross-appeal nor to obtain a certificate of appealability. We
reverse the judgment of the Fifth Circuit and remand the case for
consideration of Jennings’ Spisak claim.
It is so ordered.
SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
_________________
No. 13–7211
_________________
ROBERT MITCHELL JENNINGS, PETITIONER v. WILLIAM STEPHENS,
DIRECTOR, TEXAS DE-PARTMENT OF CRIMINAL JUSTICE, COR-RECTIONAL
INSTITUTIONS DIVISION
on writ of certiorari to the united states court of appeals for
the fifth circuit
[January 14, 2015]
Justice Thomas, with whom Justice Kennedy and Justice Alito
join, dissenting.
The Court holds today that a prisoner who obtains an order for
his release unless the State grants him a new sentencing proceeding
may, as an appellee, raise any alternative argument rejected below
that could have resulted in a similar order. In doing so, the
majority mistakenly equates a judgment granting a
conditional-release order with an ordinary civil judgment. I
respectfully dissent.
I
Title28 U. S. C. §2253(c)(1)(A), as amended by the
Antiterrorism and Effective Death Penalty Act of 1996 (AEDPA),
provides in relevant part: “Unless a circuit justice or judge
issues a certificate of appealability, an appeal may not be taken
to the court of appeals from . . . the final order in a
habeas corpus proceeding in which the detention complained of
arises out of process issued by a State court.” Further, “[a]
certificate of appealability may issue . . . only if the
applicant has made a substantial showing of the denial of a
constitutional right,” and the certificate must “indicate which
specific issue or issues satisfy [that] showing.” §§2253(c)(2),(3).
Because Jennings did not obtain a certificate of appealability
(COA), we must consider whether, by raising his “cross-point,” he
took an appeal within the meaning of AEDPA.
I agree with the majority that if a habeas petitioner takes what
is, in substance or in form, a cross-appeal to the Court of
Appeals, then he must obtain a COA. The failure to obtain a COA is
a jurisdictional bar to review. See Gonzalez v.
Thaler, 565 U. S. ___, ___ (2012) (slip op., at 8). The
critical question the Court faces is whether Jennings’
“cross-point” was in fact a cross-appeal.
II
A
The majority correctly identifies the rule we apply to determine
whether a party has taken a cross-appeal, United States v.
American Railway Express Co.,265 U. S. 425,435 (1924),
but then fails to apply it in accordance with the history of the
writ of habeas corpus, our precedents concerning
conditional-release orders, and traditional principles governing
equitable relief. Each of these guides supports the conclusion that
a prisoner who obtains a conditional-release order allowing the
State to resentence him in a new proceeding is entitled, if the
State elects that option, to a new sentencing proceeding free of
the specific constitutional violation identified by the district
court. Because a conditional-release order embodies this specific
right, an appellee’s attempt to add additional errors is an attempt
to modify or expand his rights under the judgment.
For most of its existence, the writ of habeas corpus was
understood far more narrowly than it is today. See Wright v.
West,505 U. S. 277–287 (1992) (opinion of Thomas, J.).
Originally, it played only a procedural role: It issued as of right
when a prisoner showed probable cause to believe he was being held
illegally—that is, without a conviction entered by a court of
competent jurisdiction over the prisoner—and obligated the warden
to file a “return” identifying the grounds of imprisonment.
W. Church, A Treatise on the Writ of Habeas Corpus §§94, 122
(rev. 2d ed. 1893) (hereinafter Church). The “grant of the writ
decided nothing except that there was a case calling for an answer
by the gaoler.” Goddard, A Note on Habeas Corpus, 65 L. Q. Rev. 30,
34 (1949). And the court’s ultimate decision on the matter was
limited to confirming the legality of the prisoner’s confinement or
ordering his immediate discharge. See Church §§130, 131.
The writ today, by contrast, is invoked to justify broad federal
review of state criminal proceedings for constitutional violations.
And, when a district court issues the writ, it usually enters a
conditional-release order, offering the State a choice between
immediate release or a retrial (or resentencing) within a defined
period of time. See Wilkinson v. Dotson,544
U. S. 74–87 (2005) (Scalia, J., concurring).
The purpose of a conditional-release order is to afford the
State an opportunity to remedy the specific constitutional
violation identified by the district court. Since its inception
over a century ago, we have treated a conditional-release order as
entitling a habeas petitioner not just toa new proceeding, but to a
new proceeding that cures the specific defect identified by the
district court. One of our earliest precedents contemplating such
an order is In re Bonner,151 U. S. 242–260 (1894).
That case involved a prisoner who had been lawfully convicted, but
unlawfully ordered to serve his federal sentence in a state
penitentiary. Id., at 254–255, 260. Invoking its “power to
control and direct the form of judgment to be entered in cases
brought up before it on habeas corpus,” the Court ordered
the delay of discharge to allow the prisoner to be “taken before
the court where the judgment was rendered, that the defects
for want of jurisdiction which are the subject of complaint
in that judgment may be corrected.” Id., at 261
(emphasis added); see also Magwood v. Patterson,561
U. S. 320,347 (2010) (Kennedy, J., joined by, inter
alios, Alito, J., dissenting) (“[A] conditional grant of relief
. . . allows the state court to correct an error that
occurred at the original sentencing”). That understanding of habeas
judgments has prevailed in an unbroken line of precedent. See
Richmond v. Lewis,506 U. S. 40,52 (1992);
Hilton v. Braunskill,481 U. S. 770,775 (1987);
Dowd v. United States ex rel. Cook,340
U. S. 206–210 (1951); Mahler v. Eby,264
U. S. 32,46 (1924). Cf. Dotson, supra, at 86
(Scalia, J., concurring) (“[T]he conditional writ serves only to
‘delay the release . . . in order to provide the State an
opportunity to correct the constitutional violation’ ”
(quoting Braunskill, supra, at 775)).
When the State fails to cure the specific constitutional
violation identified by the district court, the habeas petitioner
is entitled to release. That is because the prevailing habeas
petitioner has shown that his conviction or sentencing proceeding
was unconstitutional and that he is therefore “actually entitled to
release.” Dotson, 544 U. S., at 86 (Scalia, J.,
concurring). “Conditional writs enable habeas courts to give States
time to replace an invalid judgment with a valid one, and the
consequence when they fail to do so is always release.” Id.,
at 87. But that entitlement to release is tied to the
constitutional violation identified by the Court. A State
committing a new constitutional violation during the new sentencing
proceeding will not be required to release the habeas petitioner
under the old order. Cf. Magwood, supra, at 339
(explaining that a habeas petitioner who obtains a new sentencing
proceeding on the basis of one error may subsequently raise, in a
first habeas application, other errors repeated in that
proceeding).
A habeas petitioner’s rights under the conditional-release order
are thus defined by the violation that justified its entry, not by
the wording of the order. Pitchess v. Davis,421
U. S. 482 (1975) (per curiam), makes that clear.
Davis involved a prisoner who had obtained habeas relief
because the prosecutor had failed to disclose a material and
exculpatory laboratory report, in violation of Brady v.
Maryland,373 U. S. 83 (1963). 421 U. S., at 483.
When the State moved to retry him, the prisoner discovered that the
State had destroyed some of the physical evidence used against him
at his initial trial. Id., at 484. The District Court
granted the prisoner’s motion to convert its initial
conditional-release order into an unconditional order. Id.,
at 485. After the Court of Appeals affirmed that decision, this
Court granted certiorari and reversed. Id., at 486, 490.
Although the conditional-release order provided only that the
prisoner should be released unless the State moved to retry him
within 60 days, Davis v. Pitchess, 388 F. Supp.
105, 114 (CD Cal. 1974), the Court read that conditional-release
order to require the State to “provid[e] respondent with the
laboratory report,” in addition to moving to retry him within
60 days, Davis, 421 U. S., at 483 (emphasis added).
Because the order did not address the separate issue of the
physical evidence, the Court refused to allow the District Court to
use its destruction as a basis for converting the
conditional-release order to an unconditional order.
That decision makes sense when considered in light of
traditional principles of equitable relief. “This Court has
frequently rested its habeas decisions on equitable principles.”
Withrow v. Williams,507 U. S. 680,717 (1993)
(Scalia, J., concurring in part and dissenting in part). (Such
principles remain relevant after AEDPA’s enactment when they are
consistent with the statutory scheme Congress adopted. See,
e.g., McQuiggin v. Perkins, 569 U. S. ___, ___ –
___ (2013) (Scalia, J., dissenting) (slip op., at 2–3).) And the
Court has frequently recognized that an equitable “remedy must
. . . be limited to the inadequacy that produced” the
asserted injury. Lewis v. Casey,518 U. S.
343,357 (1996). Thus, a conditional-release order will not “permit
a federal habeas court to maintain a continuing supervision over a
retrial conducted pursuant to a conditional writ granted by the
habeas court.” Davis, 421 U. S., at 490. But neither
will a conditional-release order permit a State to hold a prisoner
under a new judgment infected by the same constitutional violation
that justified the order’s entry in the first place. See
Dotson, supra, at 87 (Scalia, J., concurring);
Harvest v. Castro, 531 F. 3d 737, 750 (CA9
2008); Phifer v. Warden, 53 F. 3d 859, 864–865
(CA7 1995). Such an interpretation of ha-beas judgments would
render the writ hollow.
The history of the writ of habeas corpus, the treatment of
conditional-release orders, and traditional principles of equitable
relief resolve the dispute at issue here. A habeas petitioner
awarded a conditional-release order based onan error at his
sentencing proceeding is entitled, under that order, to a new
proceeding without the specific constitutional violation identified
by the district court. Raising any other constitutional violation
on appeal would be an attempt to modify the prisoner’s rights
flowing from that order.
B
Given these principles, the judgment of the Court of Appeals
should be affirmed. Jennings prevailed in the District Court on two
theories of ineffective assistance of counsel and lost on another.
The District Court entered a conditional-release order instructing
the State to release Jennings unless it granted Jennings a new
sentencing hearing within 120 days or commuted his sentence.
Ante, at 5. Under this Court’s precedents, that general
order embodies a specific instruction to the State with respect to
a new sentencing proceeding: resentence Jennings without the two
identified Wiggins errors. See ante, at 3 (citing
Wiggins v. Smith,539 U. S. 510 (2003)). The
State’s failure to comply with that order would justify Jennings’
release. Jennings attempted, through his cross-point, to expand his
rights under the judgment when he attempted to alter the
instruction to the State—adding an additional instruction about a
Spisak error—and, accordingly, the grounds upon which he
could obtain immediate release. See ante, at 3 (citing
Smith v. Spisak,558 U. S. 139 (2010)). Jennings’
cross-point was in substance a cross-appeal for which he needed to
obtain a COA.
III
A
The majority makes no attempt to reconcile its decision with the
history of conditional-release orders, our precedents, or
traditional limitations on equitable relief. Nor could it. Instead,
it divines an “intuitive answer” to the question presented,
ante, at 5, from the law of judgments. But not only is this
the incorrect source of law, the major-ity’s position is
fundamentally at odds with the law of judgments on which it
purports to rely.
The majority agrees that, to understand how the cross-appeal
rule applies in a given case, one must understand the rights that
parties obtained under the judgment at issue. But the majority
refuses to look past the language of the conditional-release order.
It is, of course, true that parties domesticate judgments, not
opinions. Ante, at 5–6. And it is similarly true that
prevailing parties enforce judgments, not reasoning. Ante,
at 6. Those truisms, however, do not answer the question here,
which is what rights flow from those judgments.
In answering that question, the majority simply announces
that the rights that flow from a habeas petitioner’s judgment are
the same rights that flow from any other civil judgment. But that
assertion ignores the unique context of habeas, in which the
traditional principles of the law of judgments have never applied.
As explained above, the writ of habeas corpus was historically a
purely procedural mechanism to obtain a court’s determination as to
the legality of a prisoner’s confinement. Church §§94, 122, 130,
131. And that determination was never treated as an ordinary civil
judgment entitled to res judicata effect. Id., §386; see
also McCleskey v. Zant,499 U. S. 467,479
(1991).
Even if the majority were correct that the law of judgments
could simply be imported to the habeas context, it misapplies that
law. Under long recognized principles, including the doctrine of
preclusion, parties have greater rights under civil judgments than
merely the particular relief afforded. A prevailing plaintiff’s
claims are wholly merged into his judgment, preventing a defendant,
in a future action on that judgment, from availing himself of
defenses that he could have raised in the court’s first
adjudication of the claims. Restatement (Second) of Judgments §18
(1980). And a defendant, whether victorious or not, can rely upon
that judgment as the final adjudication of a particular claim,
preventing the plaintiff from pursuing another action against him
in the future on that same claim. Id., §19. These principles
give rights to the parties beyond the remedy ordered. By narrowly
and artificially defining the rights flowing from a civil judgment
as solely those rights identified in a written order, the majority
disregards these basic principles. And because the majority
purports to apply the general law of judgments, its decision will
do damage well beyond the habeas context in which this case
arises.
B
In the habeas context specifically, the majority’s opinion
invites the same frivolous appeals that Congress passed AEDPA to
prevent. Although courts had long relied on the certificate of
probable cause as a mechanism to prevent frivolous appeals in
habeas cases, AEDPA further narrowed access to such appeals with
the creation of the COA requirement. Miller-El v.
Cockrell,537 U. S. 322,356 (2003) (Thomas, J.,
dissenting). A habeas petitioner cannot obtain a COA absent a
substantial showing of the denial of a constitutional, not
merely federal, right. See Slack v. McDaniel,529
U. S. 473–484 (2000). This requirement serves an important
gatekeeping function. But the majority’s decision will seriously
undermine the courts’ ability to perform this function by allowing
prisoners to pursue any alternative allegation, no matter
how frivolous, that would have justified the same new proceeding
awarded in the conditional-release order below.
This danger is by no means “exaggerated,” ante, at 7, as
the majority suggests. Habeas petitioners frequently pursue 20 or
more arguments on collateral review, even though they could more
effectively concentrate on a handful of arguments. See,
e.g., Calvert v. Henderson, 2012 WL 1033632,
*1 (ED La., Mar. 27, 2012) (raising 26 allegations of ineffective
assistance of counsel); Battle v. Roper, 2009 WL
799604, *13 (ED Mo., Mar. 24, 2009) (raising 1 double jeopardy
issue and 20 allegations of ineffective assistance of counsel). I
see little reason to suspect that the prisoners who file these
scattershot applications will suddenly alter their strategy on
appeal. Indeed, the experience of the Courts of Appeals suggests
otherwise. See, e.g., Jones v. Keane, 329 F. 3d
290, 296 (CA2 2003) (noting, but refusing to consider absent a COA,
a prevailing ha-beas petitioner’s “alternative grounds” for
affirmance—allegations of insufficiency of the evidence and
ineffective assistance of both trial and appellate counsel). And
the experience of the Courts of Appeals with this conduct is only
likely to grow now that the majority has approved it. Where before
only the United States Court of Appeals for the Seventh Circuit had
permitted prevailing habeas petitioners to raise rejected claims as
alternative grounds for affirmance, now all Courts of Appeals will
be subject to that rule.
The majority also overlooks a significant procedural distinction
between an application for a COA and a merits appeal. The majority
expresses “doubt that any more judicial time will be wasted in
rejection of frivolous claims made in defense of judgment on an
appeal already taken than would be wasted in rejection of similar
claims made in . . . a separate proceeding for a
certificate of appealability.” Ante, at 8. But a COA can be
decided by a single court of appeals judge,28 U. S. C.
§2253(c)(1), while a merits appeal must be heard by a three-judge
panel. By mandating the involvement of two additional judges in the
adjudication of these claims, today’s ruling triples the
burden on the Courts of Appeals.
* * *
This Court has repeatedly recognized that AEDPA’s purpose is to
“reduc[e] delays in the execution of state and federal criminal
sentences.” Ryan v. Valencia Gonzales, 568 U. S.
___, ___ (2013) (slip op., at 17) (internal quotation marks
omitted). One of the key ways in which AEDPA encourages finality is
to narrow the scope of appellate review by requiring habeas
petitioners to obtain COAs. The majority’s decision undermines that
legislative choice and, in so doing, transforms the understandingof
conditional-release orders that has prevailed sincethe Court first
announced their creation. I respectfully dissent.