Appellee Michigan State Chamber of Commerce is a nonprofit
corporation, whose bylaws set forth both political and nonpolitical
purposes. Its general treasury is funded through annual dues
required of all members, three-quarters of whom are for-profit
corporations. Section 54(1) of the Michigan Campaign Finance Act
prohibits corporations, excluding media corporations, from using
general treasury funds for,
inter alia, independent
expenditures in connection with state candidate elections. However,
they may make such expenditures from segregated funds used solely
for political purposes. Because the Chamber wished to use general
treasury funds to place a local newspaper advertisement in support
of a specific candidate for state office, it brought suit in the
Federal District Court for injunctive relief against § 54(1)'s
enforcement, arguing that the expenditure restrictions are
unconstitutional under the First and Fourteenth Amendments. The
court upheld the section, but the Court of Appeals reversed,
reasoning that, as applied to the Chamber, § 54(1) violated
the First Amendment.
Held:
1. Section 54(1) does not violate the First Amendment. Pp.
494 U. S.
657-666.
(a) Although § 54(1)'s requirements burden the Chamber's
exercise of political expression,
see FEC v. Massachusetts
Citizens for Life, Inc., 479 U. S. 238,
479 U. S. 252
(
MCFL), they are justified by a compelling state interest:
preventing corruption or the appearance of corruption in the
political arena by reducing the threat that huge corporate
treasuries, which are amassed with the aid of favorable state laws
and have little or no correlation to the public's support for the
corporation's political ideas, will be used to influence unfairly
election outcomes. Pp.
494 U. S.
657-660
(b) Section 54(1) is sufficiently narrowly tailored to achieve
its goal, because it is precisely targeted to eliminate the
distortion caused by corporate spending while also allowing
corporations to express their political views by making
expenditures through separate segregated funds. Because persons who
contribute to segregated funds understand that their money will be
used solely for political purposes, the speech generated accurately
reflects contributors' support for the corporation's political
views. The fact that § 54(1) covers closely held corporations
that
Page 494 U. S. 653
do not possess vast reservoirs of capital does not make it
substantially overinclusive, because all corporations receive the
special benefits conferred by the corporate form and thus present
the potential for distorting the political process.
Cf. FEC v.
National Right to Work Committee, 459 U.
S. 197,
459 U. S.
209-210. Pp.
494 U. S.
660-661.
(c) There is no merit to the Chamber's argument that, even if
§ 54(1) is constitutional with respect to for-profit
corporations, it cannot be applied to a nonprofit ideological
corporation such as itself. The Chamber does not exhibit the
crucial features identified in
MCFL, supra, that would
require the State to exempt it from independent spending burdens as
a nonprofit corporation more akin to a voluntary political
association than a business firm.
MCFL's narrow focus on
the promotion of political ideas ensured that its resources
reflected political support, while the Chamber's more varied bylaws
do not. Additionally, unlike
MCFL members, the Chamber's
members are similar to shareholders -- who have an economic
disincentive for disassociating with a corporation even if they
disagree with its political activity -- in that they may be
reluctant to withdraw from the Chamber because they wish to benefit
from its nonpolitical programs and to establish contacts with other
members of the business community. Also in contrast to MCFL, which
took no contributions from business corporations, more than
three-quarters of the Chamber's members are business corporations,
whose political contributions and expenditures can constitutionally
be regulated by the State, and who thus could circumvent §
54(1)'s restrictions by funneling money through the Chamber's
general treasury. Pp.
494 U. S.
661-665.
(d) Section 54(1) is not rendered under-inclusive by its failure
to regulate the independent expenditures of unincorporated labor
unions that also have the capacity to accumulate wealth, because
the exclusion does not undermine the State's compelling interest in
regulating corporations whose unique form enhances such capacity.
Moreover, because members who disagree with a union's political
activities can decline to contribute to them without giving up
other membership benefits, a union's political funds more
accurately reflect members' support for the organization's
political views than does a corporation's general treasury. Pp.
494 U. S.
665-666.
2. Section 54(1) does not violate the Equal Protection Clause of
the Fourteenth. Amendment. Even under strict scrutiny, its
classifications pass muster. The State's decision to regulate
corporations and not unincorporated associations is precisely
tailored to serve its compelling interest. Similarly, the exemption
of media corporations does not render the section unconstitutional.
Restrictions on the expenditures of corporations whose resources
are devoted to the collection and dissemination of information to
the public might discourage news broadcasters or
Page 494 U. S. 654
publishers from serving their crucial societal role of reporting
on and publishing editorials about newsworthy events; thus, their
exemption from the section's restrictions is justified. Pp.
494 U. S.
666-668.
856 F.2d 783 (CA6 1988), reversed.
MARSHALL, J., delivered the opinion of the Court, in which
REHNQUIST, C.J., and BRENNAN, WHITE, BLACKMUN, and STEVENS, JJ.,
joined. BRENNAN, J.,
post, p.
494 U. S. 669,
and STEVENS, J.,
post, p.
494 U. S. 678,
filed concurring opinions. SCALIA, J., filed a dissenting opinion,
post, p.
494 U. S. 679.
KENNEDY, J., filed a dissenting opinion, in which O'CONNOR and
SCALIA, JJ., joined,
post, p.
494 U. S.
695.
Justice MARSHALL delivered the opinion of the Court.
In this appeal, we must determine whether § 54(1) of the
Michigan Campaign Finance Act violates either the First or the
Fourteenth Amendment to the Constitution. Section 54(1) prohibits
corporations from using corporate treasury funds for independent
expenditures in support of or in opposition to any candidate in
elections for state office. Mich.Comp. Laws § 169.254(1)
(1979). Corporations
Page 494 U. S. 655
are allowed, however, to make such expenditures from segregated
funds used solely for political purposes. § 169.255(1). In
response to a challenge brought by the Michigan State Chamber of
Commerce, the Sixth Circuit held that § 54(1) could not be
applied to the Chamber, a Michigan nonprofit corporation, without
violating the First Amendment. 856 F.2d 783 (1988). Although we
agree that expressive rights are implicated in this case, we hold
that application of § 54(1) to the Chamber is constitutional
because the provision is narrowly tailored to serve a compelling
state interest. Accordingly, we reverse the judgment of the Court
of Appeals.
I
Section 54(1) of the Michigan Campaign Finance Act prohibits
corporations from making contributions and independent expenditures
in connection with state candidate elections. [
Footnote 1] The issue before us is only the
constitutionality of the State's ban on independent expenditures.
The Act defines "expenditure" as
"a payment, donation, loan, pledge, or promise of payment of
money or anything of ascertainable monetary value for goods,
materials, services, or facilities in assistance of, or in
opposition to, the nomination or election of a candidate."
§ 169.206(1). An expenditure is considered independent if
it is "not made at the direction of, or under the control of,
another person and if the expenditure is not a contribution to a
committee." § 169.209(1);
see § 169.203(4)
(defining "committee" as a group that "receives contributions or
makes expenditures for the purpose of influencing or attempting to
influence the action of the voters for or against the nomination or
election of a candidate"). The Act exempts from this general
prohibition against corporate political spending any expenditure
made from a segregated fund.
Page 494 U. S. 656
§ 169.255(1). A corporation may solicit contributions to
its political fund only from an enumerated list of persons
associated with the corporation.
See §§
169.255(2), (3).
The Michigan State Chamber of Commerce, a nonprofit Michigan
corporation, challenges the constitutionality of this statutory
scheme. The Chamber comprises more than 8,000 members,
three-quarters of whom are for-profit corporations. The Chamber's
general treasury is funded through annual dues required of all
members. Its purposes, as set out in the bylaws, are to promote
economic conditions favorable to private enterprise; to analyze,
compile, and disseminate information about laws of interest to the
business community and to publicize to the government the views of
the business community on such matters; to train and educate its
members; to foster ethical business practices; to collect data on
and investigate matters of social, civic, and economic importance
to the State; to receive contributions and to make expenditures for
political purposes and to perform any other lawful political
activity; and to coordinate activities with other similar
organizations.
In June 1985, Michigan scheduled a special election to fill a
vacancy in the Michigan House of Representatives. Although the
Chamber had established and funded a separate political fund, it
sought to use its general treasury funds to place in a local
newspaper an advertisement supporting a specific candidate. As the
Act made such an expenditure punishable as a felony,
see
§ 169.254(5), the Chamber brought suit in District Court for
injunctive relief against enforcement of the Act, arguing that the
restriction on expenditures is unconstitutional under both the
First and the Fourteenth Amendments.
The District Court upheld the statute.
643 F.
Supp. 397 (WD Mich.1986). The Sixth Circuit reversed, reasoning
that the expenditure restrictions, as applied to the Chamber,
violated the First Amendment. We noted probable jurisdiction, 490
U.S. 1045 (1989), and now reverse.
Page 494 U. S. 657
II
To determine whether Michigan's restrictions on corporate
political expenditures may constitutionally be applied to the
Chamber, we must ascertain whether they burden the exercise of
political speech and, if they do, whether they are narrowly
tailored to serve a compelling state interest.
Buckley v.
Valeo, 424 U. S. 1,
424 U. S. 44-45
(1976) (per curiam). Certainly, the use of funds to support a
political candidate is "speech" independent campaign expenditures
constitute "political expression
at the core of our electoral
process and of the First Amendment freedoms.'" Id. at
424 U. S. 39
(quoting Williams v. Rhodes, 393 U. S.
23, 393 U. S. 32
(1968)). The mere fact that the Chamber is a corporation does not
remove its speech from the ambit of the First Amendment. See,
e.g., First National Bank of Boston v. Bellotti, 435 U.
S. 765, 435 U. S. 777
(1978).
This Court concluded in
FEC v. Massachusetts Citizens for
Life, Inc., 479 U. S. 238
(1986) (
MCFL), that a federal statute requiring
corporations to make independent political expenditures only
through special segregated funds, 2 U.S.C. § 441b, burdens
corporate freedom of expression.
MCFL, 479 U.S. at
479 U. S. 252
(plurality opinion);
id. at
479 U. S. 266
(O'CONNOR, J., concurring in part and concurring in judgment). The
Court reasoned that the small nonprofit corporation in that case
would face certain organizational and financial hurdles in
establishing and administering a segregated political fund. For
example, the statute required the corporation to appoint a
treasurer for its segregated fund, keep records of all
contributions, file a statement of organization containing
information about the fund, and update that statement periodically.
Id. at
479 U. S. 253
(plurality opinion). In addition, the corporation was permitted to
solicit contributions to its segregated fund only from "members,"
which did not include persons who merely contributed to or
indicated support for the organization.
Id. at
479 U. S. 254
(plurality opinion).
Page 494 U. S. 658
These hurdles "impose[d] administrative costs that many small
entities [might] be unable to bear" and "create[d] a disincentive
for such organizations to engage in political speech."
Ibid;
see also id. at
479 U. S.
265-266 (O'CONNOR, J ).
Despite the Chamber's success in administering its separate
political fund,
see, e.g., Tr. 443 (Chamber expected to
have over $140,000 in its segregated fund available for use in the
1986 elections), Michigan's segregated fund requirement still
burdens the Chamber's exercise of expression because "the
corporation is not free to use its general funds for campaign
advocacy purposes ."
MCFL, supra, at
479 U. S. 252
(plurality opinion). The Act imposes requirements similar to those
in the federal statute involved in
MCFL: a segregated fund
must have a treasurer, § 169.221, and its administrators must
keep detailed accounts of contributions, § 169.224, and file
with state officials a statement of organization,
ibid. In
addition, a nonprofit corporation like the Chamber may solicit
contributions to its political fund only from members, stockholders
of members, officers or directors of members, and the spouses of
any of these persons. § 169.255. Although these requirements
do not stifle corporate speech entirely, they do burden expressive
activity.
See MCFL, 479 U.S. at
479 U. S. 252
(plurality opinion);
id. at
479 U. S. 266
(O'CONNOR, J.). Thus, they must be justified by a compelling state
interest.
B
The State contends that the unique legal and economic
characteristics of corporations necessitate some regulation of
their political expenditures to avoid corruption or the appearance
of corruption.
See FEC v. National Conservative Political
Action Comm., 470 U. S. 480,
470 U. S.
496-497 (1985) (NCPAC) ("[P]reventing corruption or the
appearance of corruption are the only legitimate and compelling
government interests thus far identified for restricting campaign
finances"). State law grants corporations special advantages --
such as limited liability, perpetual life, and favorable
Page 494 U. S. 659
treatment of the accumulation and distribution of assets -- that
enhance their ability to attract capital and to deploy their
resources in ways that maximize the return on their shareholders'
investments. These state-created advantages not only allow
corporations to play a dominant role in the nation's economy, but
also permit them to use "resources amassed in the economic
marketplace" to obtain "an unfair advantage in the political
marketplace. "
MCFL, 479 U.S. at
479 U. S. 257.
As the Court explained in
MCFL, the political advantage of
corporations is unfair because
"[t]he resources in the treasury of a business corporation . . .
are not an indication of popular support for the corporation's
political ideas. They reject instead the economically motivated
decisions of investors and customers. The availability of these
resources may make a corporation a formidable political presence,
even though the power of the corporation may be no reflection of
the power of its ideas."
Id. at
479 U. S. 258.
We therefore have recognized that
"the compelling governmental interest in preventing corruption
support[s] the restriction of the influence of political war chests
funneled through the corporate form."
NCPAC, supra, 470 U.S. at
470 U. S.
500-501;
see also MCFL, supra, 479 U.S. at
479 U. S.
257.
The Chamber argues that this concern about corporate domination
of the political process is insufficient to justify restrictions on
independent expenditures. Although this Court has distinguished
these expenditures from direct contributions in the context of
federal laws regulating individual donors,
Buckley, 424
U.S. at
424 U. S. 47, it
has also recognized that a legislature might demonstrate a danger
of real or apparent corruption posed by such expenditures when made
by corporations to influence candidate elections,
Bellotti, 435 U.S. at
435 U. S. 788,
n. 26. Regardless of whether this danger of "financial
quid pro
quo " corruption,
see NCPAC, supra, 470 U.S. at
470 U. S. 497;
post at
494 U. S.
702-705 (KENNEDY, J., dissenting), may be sufficient to
justify a restriction on independent expenditures, Michigan's
regulation
Page 494 U. S. 660
aims at a different type of corruption in the political arena:
the corrosive and distorting effects of immense aggregations of
wealth that are accumulated with the help of the corporate form and
that have little or no correlation to the public's support for the
corporation's political ideas.
See supra at
494 U. S.
658-659. The Act does not attempt "to equalize the
relative influence of speakers on elections,"
post at
494 U. S. 705
(KENNEDY, J., dissenting);
see also post at
494 U. S. 684
(SCALIA, J., dissenting); rather, it ensures that expenditures
reflect actual public support for the political ideas espoused by
corporations. We emphasize that the mere fact that corporations may
accumulate large amounts of wealth is not the justification for
§ 54; rather, the unique state-conferred corporate structure
that facilitates the amassing of large treasuries warrants the
limit on independent expenditures. Corporate wealth can unfairly
influence elections when it is deployed in the form of independent
expenditures, just as it can when it assumes the guise of political
contributions. We therefore hold that the State has articulated a
sufficiently compelling rationale to support its restriction on
independent expenditures by corporations.
C
We next turn to the question whether the Act is sufficiently
narrowly tailored to achieve its goal. We find that the Act is
precisely targeted to eliminate the distortion caused by corporate
spending while also allowing corporations to express their
political views. Contrary to the dissents' critical assumptions,
see post at
494 U. S. 698,
494 U. S. 699,
494 U. S. 706
(KENNEDY, J., dissenting);
post at
494 U. S. 680,
494 U. S.
682-683 (SCALIA, J., dissenting), the Act does not
impose an absolute ban on all forms of corporate political
spending, but permits corporations to make independent political
expenditures through separate segregated funds. Because persons
contributing to such funds understand that their money will be used
solely for political purposes, the speech generated accurately
reflects contributors' support
Page 494 U. S. 661
for the corporation's political views.
See MCFL, supra,
479 U.S. at
479 U. S.
258.
The Chamber argues that § 54(1) is substantially
overinclusive, because it includes within its scope closely held
corporations that do not possess vast reservoirs of capital. We
rejected a similar argument in
FEC v. National Right to Work
Committee, 459 U. S. 197
(1982) (
NRWC), in the context of federal restrictions on
the persons from whom corporations could solicit contributions to
their segregated funds. The Court found that the federal campaign
statute, 2 U.S.C. § 441b,
"reflect[ed] a legislative judgment that the special
characteristics of the corporate structure require particularly
careful regulation. While § 441b restricts the solicitation of
corporations and labor unions without great financial resources, as
well as those more fortunately situated, we accept Congress'
judgment that it is the
potential for such influence that
demands regulation."
459 U.S. at
459 U. S.
209-210 (citation omitted; emphasis added). Although
some closely held corporations, just as some publicly held ones,
may not have accumulated significant amounts of wealth, they
receive from the State the special benefits conferred by the
corporate structure and present the potential for distorting the
political process. This potential for distortion justifies §
54(1)'s general applicability to all corporations. The section
therefore is not substantially overbroad.
III
The Chamber contends that even if the Campaign Finance Act is
constitutional with respect to for-profit corporations, it
nonetheless cannot be applied to a nonprofit ideological
corporation like a chamber of commerce. In
MCFL, we held
that the nonprofit organization there had
"features more akin to voluntary political associations than
business firms, and therefore should not have to bear burdens on
independent spending solely because of [its] incorporated
status."
479 U.S. at
479 U. S. 263.
In reaching that conclusion, we enumerated
Page 494 U. S. 662
three characteristics of the corporation that were "essential"
to our holding.
Ibid. Because the Chamber does not share
these crucial features, the Constitution does not require that it
be exempted from the generally applicable provisions of §
54(1).
The first characteristic of Massachusetts Citizens for Life,
Inc., that distinguished it from ordinary business corporations was
that the organization "was formed for the express purpose of
promoting political ideas, and cannot engage in business
activities."
Id. at
479 U. S. 264.
Its articles of incorporation indicated that its purpose was
"[t]o foster respect for human life and to defend the right to
life of all human beings, born and unborn, through educational,
political and other forms of activities,"
id. at
479 U. S.
241-242, and all of the organization's activities were
"designed to further its agenda,"
id. at 242.
MCFL's narrow political focus thus "ensure[d] that [its]
political resources reflect[ed] political support."
Id. at
479 U. S.
264.
In contrast, the Chamber's bylaws set forth more varied
purposes,
see supra at
494 U. S. 656,
several of which are not inherently political. For instance, the
Chamber compiles and disseminates information relating to social,
civic, and economic conditions, trains and educates its members,
and promotes ethical business practices. Unlike
MCFL's,
the Chamber's educational activities are not expressly tied to
political goals; many of its seminars, conventions, and
publications are politically neutral and focus on business and
economic issues. The Chamber's President and Chief Executive
Officer stated that one of the corporation's main purposes is to
provide
"service to [its] membership that includes everything from group
insurance to educational seminars, and . . . litigation activities
on behalf of the business community."
Deposition of E. James Barrett, Nov. 12, 1985, p. 11.
See
also PR Newswire, July 21, 1989 (Chamber cosponsored the
Automotive Management Briefing Seminar); PR Newswire, May 9, 1989
(Chamber cosponsored the Michigan New Product Awards
Page 494 U. S. 663
competition); PR Newswire, June 14, 1988 (Chamber sponsored
seminar on product liability losses and lawsuits); PR Newswire,
Feb. 4, 1988 (Chamber cosponsored outreach program to increase
awareness of investment opportunities in the Caribbean Basin). The
Chamber's nonpolitical activities therefore suffice to distinguish
it from
MCFL in the context of this characteristic.
We described the second feature of
MCFL as the absence
of "shareholders or other persons affiliated so as to have a claim
on its assets or earnings. This ensures that persons connected with
the organization will have no economic disincentive for
disassociating with it if they disagree with its political
activity." 479 U.S. at
479 U. S. 264.
Although the Chamber also lacks shareholders, many of its members
may be similarly reluctant to withdraw as members even if they
disagree with the Chamber's political expression, because they wish
to benefit from the Chamber's nonpolitical programs and to
establish contacts with other members of the business community.
The Chamber's political agenda is sufficiently distinct from its
educational and outreach programs that members who disagree with
the former may continue to pay dues to participate in the latter.
Justice KENNEDY ignores these disincentives for withdrawing as a
member of the Chamber, stating only that "[o]ne need not become a
member . . . to earn a living."
Post at
494 U. S. 710
(KENNEDY, J., dissenting). Certainly, members would be disinclined
to terminate their involvement with the organization on the basis
of less extreme disincentives than the loss of employment. Thus, we
are persuaded that the Chamber's members are more similar to
shareholders of a business corporation than to the members of
MCFL in this respect. [
Footnote 2]
Page 494 U. S. 664
The final characteristic upon which we relied in
MCFL
was the organization's independence from the influence of business
corporations. On this score, the Chamber differs most greatly from
the Massachusetts organization.
MCFL was not established
by, and had a policy of not accepting contributions from, business
corporations. Thus it could not "serv[e] as [a] condui[t] for the
type of direct spending that creates a threat to the political
marketplace."
Ibid. In striking contrast, more than
three-quarters of the Chamber's members are business corporations,
whose political contributions and expenditures can constitutionally
be regulated by the State.
See Buckley v. Valeo, 424 U.S.
at
424 U. S. 29
(upholding restrictions on political contributions);
supra, at
494 U. S.
658-661 (regarding independent expenditures). As we read
the Act, a corporation's payments into the Chamber's general
treasury would not be considered payments to influence an election,
so they would not be "contributions" or "expenditures,"
see §§ 169.204(1), 169.206, and would not be
subject to the Act's limitations. Business corporations therefore
could circumvent the Act's restrictions by funneling money through
the Chamber's general treasury. [
Footnote 3] Because the Chamber accepts money from
for-profit corporations, it could, absent application of §
54(1), serve as a conduit for corporate political spending. In sum,
the Chamber does not possess the features
Page 494 U. S. 665
that would compel the State to exempt it from restrictions on
independent political expenditures.
IV
The Chamber also attacks § 54(1) as under-inclusive because
it does not regulate the independent expenditures of unincorporated
labor unions. [
Footnote 4] I
Whereas unincorporated unions, and indeed individuals, may be able
to amass large treasuries, they do so without the significant
state-conferred advantages of the corporate structure; corporations
are "by far the most prominent example of entities that enjoy legal
advantages enhancing their ability to accumulate wealth."
MCFL, 479 U.S. at
479 U. S. 258, n. 11. The desire to counterbalance those
advantages unique to the corporate form is the State's compelling
interest in this case; thus, excluding from the statute's coverage
unincorporated entities that also have the capacity to accumulate
wealth "does not undermine its justification for regulating
corporations."
Ibid.
Moreover, labor unions differ from corporations in that union
members who disagree with a union's political activities need not
give up full membership in the organization to avoid supporting its
political activities. Although a union and an employer may require
that all bargaining unit employees become union members, a union
may not compel those employees to support financially "union
activities beyond those germane to collective bargaining, contract
administration, and grievance adjustment."
Communications
Workers of Am. v. Beck, 487 U. S. 735,
487 U. S. 745
(1988).
See also Abood v. Detroit Bd. of Educ.,
431 U. S. 209
(1977) (holding that compelling nonmember employees to contribute
to union's political activities infringes employees' First
Amendment rights). An employee who objects to a union's political
activities thus can decline to contribute to those activities,
while continuing to enjoy the
Page 494 U. S. 666
benefits derived from the union's performance of its duties as
the exclusive representative of the bargaining unit on
labor-management issues. As a result, the funds available for a
union's political activities more accurately reflects members'
support for the organization's political views than does a
corporation's general treasury. Michigan's decision to exclude
unincorporated labor unions from the scope of § 54(1) is
therefore justified by the crucial differences between unions and
corporations.
V
Because we hold that § 54(1) does not violate the First
Amendment, we must address the Chamber's contention that the
provision infringes its rights under the Fourteenth Amendment. The
Chamber argues that the statute treats similarly situated entities
unequally. Specifically, it contends that the State should also
restrict the independent expenditures of unincorporated
associations with the ability to accumulate large treasuries and of
corporations engaged in the media business.
Because the right to engage in political expression is
fundamental to our constitutional system, statutory classifications
impinging upon that right must be narrowly tailored to serve a
compelling governmental interest.
Police Department of Chicago
v. Mosley, 408 U. S. 92,
408 U. S. 101
(1972). We find that, even under such strict scrutiny, the
statute's classifications pass muster under the Equal Protection
Clause. As we explained in the context of our discussions of
whether the statute was overinclusive,
supra at
494 U. S.
660-661, or under-inclusive,
supra at
494 U. S. 665,
the State's decision to regulate only corporations is precisely
tailored to serve the compelling state interest of eliminating from
the political process the corrosive effect of political "war
chests" amassed with the aid of the legal advantages given to
corporations.
Similarly, we find that the Act's exemption of media
corporations from the expenditure restrictions does not render the
statute unconstitutional. The "media exception" excludes
Page 494 U. S. 667
from the definition of "expenditure" any
"expenditure by a broadcasting station, newspaper, magazine, or
other periodical or publication for any news story, commentary, or
editorial in support of or opposition to a candidate for elective
office . . . in the regular course of publication or
broadcasting,"
§ 169.206(3)(d). [
Footnote
5] The Court of Appeals did not address the Chamber's equal
protection argument because it found that the application of §
54(1) to the Chamber violates the First Amendment.
See 856
F.2d at 790. The District Court, however, appeared to hold that the
media exception does not implicate the Equal Protection Clause
because "[a]ny corporation . . . may avail itself of the exemption"
by entering the news broadcasting or publishing business. 643 F.
Supp. at 405. We are persuaded, however, that a Fourteenth
Amendment analysis is necessary in this case. It is true that the
exemption does not refer expressly to "media corporations."
Nevertheless, the exception will undoubtedly result in the
imposition of fewer restrictions on the expression of corporations
that are in the media business. Thus, it cannot be regarded as
neutral, and the distinction must be justified by a compelling
state purpose.
Although all corporations enjoy the same state-conferred
benefits inherent in the corporate form, media corporations differ
significantly from other corporations in that their resources are
devoted to the collection of information and its dissemination to
the public. We have consistently recognized the unique role that
the press plays in "informing and educating the public, offering
criticism, and providing a forum for discussion and debate."
Bellotti, 435 U.S. at
435 U. S. 781.
See also Mills v. Alabama, 384 U.
S. 214,
384 U. S. 219
(1966)
Page 494 U. S. 668
("[T]he press serves and was designed to serve as a powerful
antidote to any abuses of power by governmental officials and as a
constitutionally chosen means for keeping officials elected by the
people responsible to all the people whom they were selected to
serve"). The Act's definition of "expenditure," § 169.206,
conceivably could be interpreted to encompass election-related news
stories and editorials. The Act's restrictions on independent
expenditures therefore might discourage incorporated news
broadcasters or publishers from serving their crucial societal
role. The media exception ensures that the Act does not hinder or
prevent the institutional press from reporting on and publishing
editorials about newsworthy events.
Cf. H.R.Rep. No.
93-1239, p. 4 (1974) (explaining a similar federal media exception,
2 U.S.C. § 431(9)(B)(i), as "assur[ing] the unfettered right
of the newspapers, TV networks, and other media to cover and
comment on political campaigns"); 15 U.S.C. §§ 1801-1804
(enacting a limited exemption from the antitrust laws for
newspapers in part because of the recognition of the special role
of the press). A valid distinction thus exists between corporations
that are part of the media industry and other corporations that are
not involved in the regular business of imparting news to the
public. Although the press' unique societal role may not entitle
the press to greater protection under the Constitution,
Bellotti, supra, 435 U.S. at
435 U. S. 782,
and n. 18, it does provide a compelling reason for the State to
exempt media corporations from the scope of political expenditure
limitations. We therefore hold that the Act does not violate the
Equal Protection Clause.
VI
Michigan identified as a serious danger the significant
possibility that corporate political expenditures will undermine
the integrity of the political process, and it has implemented a
narrowly tailored solution to that problem. By requiring
corporations to make all independent political expenditures
Page 494 U. S. 669
through a separate fund made up of money solicited expressly for
political purposes, the Michigan Campaign Finance Act reduces the
threat that huge corporate treasuries amassed with the aid of
favorable state laws will be used to influence unfairly the outcome
of elections. The Michigan Chamber of Commerce does not exhibit the
characteristics identified in
MCFL that would require the
State to exempt it from generally applicable restrictions on
independent corporate expenditures. We therefore reverse the
decision of the Court of Appeals.
It is so ordered.
[
Footnote 1]
Section 54(1) is modeled on a provision of the Federal Election
Campaign Act of 1971, 86 Stat. 11,
as amended, 2 U.S.C.
§§ 431-455, that requires corporations and labor unions
to use segregated funds to finance independent expenditures made in
federal elections. § 441b.
[
Footnote 2]
A requirement that the Chamber disclose the nature and extent of
its political activities,
see post at
494 U. S. 707
(KENNEDY, J., dissenting), would not eliminate the possible
distortion of the political process inherent in independent
expenditures from general corporate funds. Given the significant
incentive for members to continue their financial support for the
Chamber in spite of their disagreement with its political agenda,
disclosure will not ensure that the funds in the Chamber's treasury
correspond to members' support for its ideas.
[
Footnote 3]
A nonprofit corporation's segregated fund, on the other hand,
apparently cannot receive contributions from corporations.
See § 169.255(3) (allowing contributions only from
"(a) Members of the corporation who are individuals. (b)
Stockholders of members of the corporation. (c) Officers or
directors of members of the corporation"). In addition, a
corporation's payment to a segregated fund would likely be
considered a contribution or expenditure because the sole purpose
of such segregated funds is to make political contributions and
expenditures, § 169.255(1). The segregated fund, therefore,
could not be used as a conduit for business corporations' political
spending.
[
Footnote 4]
The Federal Election Campaign Act restricts the independent
expenditures of labor organizations as well as those of
corporations. 2 U.S.C. § 441b(a).
[
Footnote 5]
The Federal Election Campaign Act contains a similar exemption
that excludes from the definition of expenditure
"any news story, commentary, or editorial distributed through
the facilities of any broadcasting station, newspaper, magazine, or
other periodical publication, unless such facilities are owned or
controlled by any political party, political committee, or
candidate."
2 U.S.C. § 431(9)(B)(i).
Justice BRENNAN, concurring.
I join the Court's opinion. As one of the "Orwellian" "censors"
derided by the dissents,
post at
494 U. S. 679
(SCALIA, J., dissenting);
post at
494 U. S. 713
(KENNEDY, J., dissenting), and as the author of our recent decision
in
FEC v. Massachusetts Citizens for Life, Inc.,
479 U. S. 238
(1986) (
MCFL), I write separately to explain my views in
this case.
The Michigan law at issue is not an across-the-board prohibition
on political participation by corporations or even a complete ban
on corporate political expenditures. Rather, the statute merely
requires those corporations wishing to make independent
expenditures in support of candidates to do so through segregated
funds or political action committees (PACs) rather than directly
from their corporate treasuries. [
Footnote 2/1] As the dissents observe, this restriction
still must be analyzed with great solicitude and care, because
independent expenditures constitute expression "
at the core of
our electoral process and of the First Amendment freedoms.'"
Buckley v. Valeo, 424 U. S. 1,
424 U. S. 39
(1976) (per curiam ) (quoting
Page 494 U. S. 670
Williams v. Rhodes, 393 U. S. 23
(1968)). I believe, however, that the dissents significantly
overstate their case in several important respects and that the
Court's decision today is faithful to our prior opinions in the
campaign financing area, particularly
MCFL.
In
MCFL, we held that a provision of the Federal
Election Campaign Act of 1971 (FECA),
as amended, 90 Stat.
490, and amended, 2 U.S.C. § 441b, similar to the Michigan law
at issue here, could not be applied constitutionally to a small,
antiabortion advocacy group. In evaluating the First Amendment
challenge, however, we
"acknowledge[d] the legitimacy of Congress' concern that
organizations that amass great wealth in the economic marketplace
not gain unfair advantage in the political marketplace."
479 U.S. at
479 U. S. 263.
Specifically, we noted that
"
[d]irect corporate spending on political activity
raises the prospect that resources amassed in the economic
marketplace may be used to provide an unfair advantage in the
political marketplace,"
because "[t]he resources in the treasury of a business
corporation . . . are not an indication of popular support for the
corporation's political ideas."
Id. at
479 U. S.
257-258 (emphasis added). Instead, these resources
reflect "the economically motivated decisions of investors and
customers."
Id. at
479 U. S. 258.
A stockholder might oppose the use of corporate funds drawn from
the general treasury -- which represents, after all, his money --
in support of a particular political candidate.
See id. at
260, citing
FEC v. National Right to Work Committee,
459 U. S. 197,
459 U. S. 208
(1982), and
Pipefitters v. United States, 407 U.
S. 385,
407 U. S.
414-415 (1972). The requirement that corporate
independent expenditures be financed through a segregated fund or
political action committee expressly established to engage in
campaign spending is designed to avert this danger.
"The resources available to [a PAC], as opposed to the corporate
treasury, in fact reflect popular support for the political
positions of the committee."
MCFL, 479 U.S. at
479 U. S. 258.
We thus adopted the "
underlying theory'" of FECA "`that
substantial general purpose
Page 494 U. S.
671
treasuries should not be diverted to political purposes'"
and that requiring funding by voluntary contributions guarantees
that "`the money collected is that intended by those who contribute
to be used for political purposes and not money diverted from
another source.'" Ibid. (quoting 117 Cong.Rec. 43381
(1971) (statement of Rep. Hansen)). [Footnote 2/2]
The PAC requirement may be unconstitutional as applied to some
corporations because they do not present the dangers at which
expenditure limitations are aimed. Indeed, we determined that
Massachusetts Citizens for Life -- the antiabortion advocacy
organization at issue in
MCFL -- fell into this category.
[
Footnote 2/3] We nevertheless
predicted that the
Page 494 U. S. 672
class of exempt organizations would be small,
see 479
U.S. at
479 U. S. 264,
and we set out three features of
MCFL that were
"essential" to our holding that it could not be bound by the
restriction on independent spending.
Id. at
479 U. S. 263.
First, the group "was formed for the express purpose of promoting
political ideas, and [could not] engage in business activities."
Id. at
479 U. S. 264.
Second, it
"ha[d] no shareholders or other persons affiliated so as to have
a claim on its assets or earnings. This ensure[d] that persons
connected with the organization [had] no economic disincentive for
disassociating with it if they disagree[d] with its political
activity."
Ibid. (footnote omitted). Third, the group
"was not established by a business corporation or a labor union,
and it [was] its policy not to accept contributions from such
entities. This prevent[ed it] from serving as [a] condui[t] for the
type of direct spending that creates a threat to the political
marketplace."
Ibid.
The majority today persuasively demonstrates that the situation
in this case is markedly different from that in
MCFL. The
Chamber is first and foremost a business association, not a
political advocacy organization.
See ante at
494 U. S.
661-665. The Michigan statute advances the interest
identified in
MCFL in two distinct ways, by preventing
both the Chamber
and other business corporations from
using the funds of other persons for purposes that those persons
may not support. First, the state law protects the small
businessperson who does not wish his or her dues to be spent in
support of political candidates, but who nevertheless wishes to
maintain an association with the Chamber because of the myriad
benefits it provides that are
Page 494 U. S. 673
unrelated to its political activities.
See ante at
494 U. S.
662-663. The bylaws state that the Chamber's "objectives
and purposes" shall be in part "[t]o analyze, compile and
disseminate information on laws and regulations of interest to the
members" and
"[t]o further the training and education of the membership by
means of educational materials, seminars, conventions, bulletins,
newsletters, reports and technical materials."
App. 43a. To attract new members, Chamber advertisements promise
a wide variety of services, including "regular and special
publications, legislative briefings, group insurance, a business
hot-line, and seminars."
Id. at 42a. Its advertising
practices indicate that even the Chamber understands that
membership is not a function of support for its political causes
alone. A member faces significant disincentives to withdraw, even
if he disagrees with the Chamber's expenditures in support of a
particular candidate.
In addition, the Michigan law protects dissenting shareholders
of business corporations that are members of the Chamber to the
extent that such shareholders oppose the use of their money, paid
as dues to the Chamber out of general corporate treasury funds, for
political campaigns.
See MCFL, supra, at
479 U. S.
260-261;
cf. post at
494 U. S. 686
(SCALIA, J., dissenting). The Michigan law prevents the Chamber
from "serv[ing] as a conduit for corporate political spending."
Ante at
494 U. S. 664.
Even Justice KENNEDY, by repeatedly using the qualifier "nonprofit"
throughout his opinion, appears to concede that the Michigan law
legitimately may be applied to for-profit business corporations, or
at least that the Court's rationale might "suffice to justify
restricting political speech by for-profit corporations."
Post at
494 U. S. 703
(KENNEDY, J., dissenting). If that is so, Justice KENNEDY's failure
to sustain the statute as applied in this case is perplexing,
because the Chamber, unlike other nonprofits such as
MCFL,
is clearly a conduit for corporations barred from making
independent expenditures
Page 494 U. S. 674
directly. [
Footnote 2/4] A
corporation cannot under Michigan law make a contribution to a PAC
out of its general treasury funds,
see ante at
494 U. S. 664,
n. 3, and we have upheld similar rules restricting the groups from
whom PACs may solicit contributions.
See FEC v. National Right
to Work Committee, 459 U.S. at
459 U. S.
207-211;
California Medical Assn. v. FEC,
453 U. S. 182,
453 U. S.
193-199 (1981) (plurality opinion). It is common ground
that a segregated fund, even if it is a "nonprofit corporation,"
cannot be used as a conduit for independent expenditures by
business corporations; I find it unremarkable that the Chamber and
other nonprofits cannot perform such a function either.
Of course, a member could resign from the Chamber and a
stockholder could divest from a business corporation that used the
Chamber as a conduit, but these options would impose a financial
sacrifice on those objecting to political expenditures. [
Footnote 2/5]
See MCFL, 479 U.S.
at
479 U. S. 260.
It is therefore irrelevant that
"[t]o the extent that members disagree with their nonprofit
corporation's policies, they can seek change from within, withhold
financial support, cease to associate with the group, or form a
rival group of their own."
Post at
494 U. S. 710
(KENNEDY, J., dissenting). Moreover, none of the alternatives
proposed by Justice KENNEDY would protect a captive
Page 494 U. S. 675
stockholder of a business corporation that used the Chamber as a
conduit. [
Footnote 2/6] While the
State may have no constitutional duty to protect the objecting
Chamber member and corporate shareholder in the absence of state
action,
cf. Abood v. Detroit Board of Education,
431 U. S. 209,
431 U. S.
232-237 (1977), the State surely has a compelling
interest in preventing a corporation it has chartered from
exploiting those who do not wish to contribute to the Chamber's
political message.
"A's right to receive information does not require the state to
permit B to steal from C the funds that alone will enable B to make
the communication."
Brudney, Business Corporations and Stockholders' Rights Under
the First Amendment, 91 Yale L.J. 235, 247 (1981).
Cf.
Communications Workers v. Beck, 487 U.
S. 735 (1988);
Machinists v. Street,
367 U. S. 740
(1961). We have long recognized the importance of state corporate
law in "protect[ing] the shareholders" of corporations chartered
within the State.
CTS Corp. v. Dynamics Corp. of America,
481 U. S. 69,
481 U. S. 91
(1987).
The Michigan law is concededly "under-inclusive" insofar as it
does not ban other types of political expenditures to which
Page 494 U. S. 676
a dissenting Chamber member or corporate shareholder might
object.
See post at
494 U. S.
685-686 (SCALIA, J., dissenting). The particular
provision at issue prohibits corporations from using treasury funds
only for making independent expenditures in support of or in
opposition to any candidate in state elections.
See ante
at
494 U. S.
655-656. A corporation remains free, for example, to use
general treasury funds to support an initiative proposal in a state
referendum. [
Footnote 2/7]
See
First National Bank of Boston v. Bellotti, 435 U.
S. 765 (1978).
I do not find this underinclusiveness fatal, for several
reasons. [
Footnote 2/8] First, as
the dissents recognize, discussions on candidate
Page 494 U. S. 677
elections lie "at the heart of political debate."
Post
at
494 U. S. 698
(KENNEDY, J., dissenting);
see also post at
494 U. S. 680,
494 U. S. 692
(SCALIA, J., dissenting). But just as speech interests are at their
zenith in this area, so too are the interests of unwilling Chamber
members and corporate shareholders forced to subsidize that speech.
The State's decision to focus on this especially sensitive context
is a justifiable one. [
Footnote
2/9]
Cf. MCFL, 479 U.S. at
479 U. S. 258,
n. 11. Second, in light of our decisions in
First National Bank
of Boston v. Bellotti, supra, Consolidated Edison Co. v. Public
Service Comm'n of New York, 447 U. S. 530,
447 U. S.
533-535 (1980), and related cases, a State cannot
prohibit corporations from making many other types of political
expenditures. One purpose of the underinclusiveness inquiry is to
ensure that the proffered state interest actually underlies the
law.
See, e.g.,
Page 494 U. S. 678
The Florida Star v. B.J.F., 491 U.
S. 524,
491 U. S. 540
(1989);
FCC v. League of Women Voters of California,
468 U. S. 364,
468 U. S. 396
(1984). But to the extent that the Michigan statute is
"under-inclusive" only because it does not regulate corporate
expenditures in referenda or other corporate expression (besides
merely commercial speech), this reflects the requirements of our
decisions rather than the lack of an important state interest on
the part of Michigan in regulating expenditures in candidate
elections. In this sense, the Michigan law is not "under-inclusive"
at all. Finally, the provision in Michigan corporate law
authorizing shareholder actions against corporate waste might serve
as a remedy for other types of political expenditures that have no
legitimate connection to the corporation's business.
See
Mich.Comp. Laws § 600.3605(1)(b) (1979); [
Footnote 2/10]
cf. Bellotti, supra, at
435 U. S.
795.
For these reasons, I concur in the Court's opinion.
[
Footnote 2/1]
In
FEC v. Massachusetts Citizens for Life, Inc.,
479 U. S. 238
(1986), we observed that the requirement that expenditures be made
through PACs
"is of course distinguishable from the complete foreclosure of
any opportunity for political speech that we invalidated in the
state referendum context in
First National Bank of Boston v.
Bellotti, 435 U. S. 765 (1978)."
479 U.S. at
479 U. S. 259,
n. 12.
[
Footnote 2/2]
We cited with approval in
First National Bank of Boston v.
Bellotti, 435 U. S. 765
(1978), a discussion of the constitutionality of restrictions on
union contributions and independent expenditures in candidate
elections:
"[T]he ban on union political contributions and expenditures is
not total, but applies only to general union funds. Contributions
and expenditures made by a separate fund financed by voluntary
contributions are specifically permitted, as are expenditures of
general funds to solicit contributions to the separate fund. In
order to engage in political discussion, a union need only convince
its members that its views are sound enough to merit a contribution
to a union political committee espousing the same political
philosophy. The necessity of convincing union members of the value
of such a contribution does not amount to a constitutionally
invalid burden. After all, if union members are so unconvinced of
the reasonableness of the union's position that they refuse to
support it, the argument for prohibiting the union from spending
dues money to support its political views is greatly strengthened.
. . . In the case of unions, the statute strikes a legitimate and
reasonable accommodation by distinguishing between the uses to
which a separate, voluntary fund and the general treasury fund may
be put."
Comment, The Regulation of Union Political Activity: Majority
and Minority Rights and Remedies, 126 U.Pa.L.Rev. 386, 409 (1977)
(cited in
Bellotti, supra, at
435 U. S. 788,
n. 26).
[
Footnote 2/3]
Justice KENNEDY is mistaken when he suggests that, by upholding
the as-applied challenge in
MCFL and rejecting it here, we
are embarking on "value-laden, content-based speech suppression
that permits some nonprofit corporate groups but not others to
engage in political speech."
Post at
494 U. S.
695-696 (KENNEDY, J., dissenting). The mere fact that
some as-applied challenges succeed while others fail does not
create a system of "speech suppression." Whether an organization
presents the threat at which the campaign finance laws are aimed
has to do with the particular characteristics of the organization
at issue, and not with the content of its speech. Of course, if a
correlation between the two factors could be shown to exist, a
group would be free to mount a First Amendment challenge on that
basis.
Cf. Buckley v. Valeo, 424 U. S.
1,
424 U. S. 97, n.
131 (1976). Neither respondent nor Justice KENNEDY's dissent has
provided any reason to believe that such a relationship exists
here.
[
Footnote 2/4]
According to Justice KENNEDY's dissent, the majority holds that
"it is now a felony in Michigan for the Sierra Club, or the
American Civil Liberties Union" to make independent expenditures.
Post at
494 U. S. 698
(KENNEDY, J., dissenting). This characterization is inaccurate. Not
only are those groups not part of the proceeding before us, but the
dissent has overlooked the central lesson of
MCFL that the
First Amendment may require exemptions, on an as-applied basis,
from expenditure restrictions. If a nonprofit corporation is formed
with the express purpose of promoting political ideas, is not
composed of members who face an economic incentive for
disassociating with it, and does not accept contributions from
business corporations or labor unions, then it would be governed by
our
MCFL holding.
[
Footnote 2/5]
In addition, shareholders in a large business corporation may
find it prohibitively expensive to monitor the activities of the
corporation to determine whether it is making expenditures to which
they object.
[
Footnote 2/6]
Justice KENNEDY's argument is also inconsistent with his focus
on nonprofit corporations. The leading theory of nonprofit
enterprises holds that the rationale for use of the nonprofit form
lies chiefly in the so-called "nondistribution constraint" --
i.e., the fact that, while ordinary business corporations
have shareholders who are allowed to receive the residual earnings
of the enterprise, the members of a nonprofit corporation are
expressly prohibited from receiving any part of the assets or
property of the corporation for themselves.
See Hansmann,
Reforming Nonprofit Corporation Law, 129 U.Pa.L.Rev. 497, 502-507,
557 (1981); Hansmann, The Role of Nonprofit Enterprise, 89 Yale
L.J. 835, 843-845 (1980). The nondistribution constraint helps
overcome contractual failure in situations where the activities of
the corporation are difficult to monitor, by removing the "profit
motive" and assuring those who contribute to and contract with the
corporation that the nonprofit's managers will not exploit
informational deficiencies to pursue their own private interests.
Hence, Justice KENNEDY's proposed reliance on a nonprofit's donors
to monitor and police the corporation's activities overlooks the
raison d'etre of the nonprofit
[
Footnote 2/7]
This very "underinclusiveness" belies the dissents' charge that
the Michigan law is a broad restriction on corporate political
expression; many avenues of communication are open to the Chamber.
In addition, the segregated fund requirement in practice has not
burdened significantly the Chamber's speech with respect to
candidate-oriented expenditures. The Chamber established a PAC in
1977 and has drawn from that fund in every election since then. The
Chamber has an eligible class of about 50,000 individuals from whom
it can solicit contributions to its PAC under the Michigan statute,
and it has been quite successful in doing so. During the 1983-1984
election cycle, the Chamber PAC raised over $102,000, and its
projected resources for the 1986 primary and general elections
amounted to more than $140,000.
See App. in No. 86-1867
(CA6), pp. 164, 184. The District Court found that
"the record in this case amply demonstrates that the Chamber PAC
frequently makes independent expenditures to influence political
elections, and those efforts have been tremendously successful in
electing Chamber PAC endorsed candidates."
App. to Juris.Statement 66a-67a.
[
Footnote 2/8]
Justice SCALIA also maintains that protection of dissenting
shareholders cannot qualify as a valid state interest because
shareholders purchase their stock on the understanding that the
corporation will use their money for any profitmaking purpose,
including support for political candidates with whom the
shareholders may not agree.
See post at
494 U. S.
686-687. We have already rejected this argument in the
context of labor unions.
See Abood v. Detroit Board of
Education, 431 U. S. 209,
431 U. S.
234-235 (1977);
Machinists v. Street,
367 U. S. 740,
367 U. S. 764
(1961). Rather than assuming that an employee accepts as "the
deal,"
post at
494 U. S. 686,
that the union will use his dues for any purpose that will advance
the interests of the bargaining unit, including political
contributions and expenditures, we have determined that
"the authority to impose dues and fees [is] restricted at least
to the 'extent of denying the unions the right, over the employee's
objection, to use his money to support political causes which he
opposes,' even though Congress was well aware that
unions had
historically expended funds in the support of political candidates
and issues."
Ellis v. Railway Clerks, 466 U.
S. 435,
466 U. S. 447
(1984) (quoting
Street, 367 U.S. at
367 U. S. 768)
(emphasis added).
Given the extensive state regulation of corporations,
shareholder expectations are always a function of
state
law. It is circular to say, as does Justice SCALIA, that
if a State did not protect shareholders, they would have
no expectation of being protected, and therefore that the State has
no legitimate interest in protecting them. Justice SCALIA concedes,
as he must, that an expenditure "not plausibly tied to [a
corporation's] ability to make money for its shareholders" can be
prohibited.
Post at
494 U. S. 691.
But States have always been permitted to define what qualifies as
"plausibly tied" to the corporation's purpose of making money,
i.e., what qualifies as "corporate waste,"
see Rogers
v. Hill, 289 U. S. 582,
289 U. S.
591-592 (1933), including wasteful speech,
see
Bellotti, 435 U.S. at
435 U. S. 795;
Cort v. Ash, 422 U. S.
66,
422 U. S. 84
(1975). I believe it entirely proper for a State to decide to
promote the ability of investors to purchase stock in corporations
without fear that their money will be used to support candidates
with whom they do not agree.
[
Footnote 2/9]
As Justice STEVENS notes in his concurring opinion today,
post at
494 U. S.
678-679, our decision in
Bellotti expressly
distinguished "state and federal laws regulating corporate
participation in partisan
candidate elections." 435 U.S.
at
435 U. S. 788,
n. 26 (emphasis added).
[
Footnote 2/10]
I express no definitive view of the proper interpretation of
this provision of state law, inasmuch as it is not part of the case
before us.
Justice STEVENS, concurring.
In my opinion, the distinction between individual expenditures
and individual contributions that the Court identified in
Buckley v. Valeo, 424 U. S. 1,
424 U. S. 45-47
(1976), should have little, if any, weight in reviewing corporate
participation in candidate elections. In that context, I believe
the danger of either the fact, or the appearance, of
quid pro
quo relationships provides an adequate justification for state
regulation of both expenditures and contributions. Moreover, as we
recognized in
First National Bank of Boston v. Bellotti,
435 U. S. 765
(1978), there is a vast difference between lobbying and debating
public issues on the one hand, and political campaigns for election
to public office on the other.
* Accordingly, I
join the Court's opinion and judgment.
Page 494 U. S. 679
*
"In addition to prohibiting corporate contributions and
expenditures for the purpose of influencing the vote on a ballot
question submitted to the voters, § 8 also proscribes
corporate contributions or expenditures 'for the purpose of aiding,
promoting or preventing the nomination or election of any person to
public office, or aiding, promoting, or antagonizing the interests
of any political party.' . . . In this respect, the statute is not
unlike many other state and federal laws regulating corporate
participation in partisan candidate elections. Appellants do not
challenge the constitutionality of laws prohibiting or limiting
corporate contributions to political candidates or committees, or
other means of influencing candidate elections.
Cf. Pipefitters
v. United States, 407 U. S. 385 (1912);
United
States v. Automobile Workers, 352 U. S.
567 (1957);
United States v. CIO, 335 U. S.
106 (1948). About half of these laws, including the
federal law, 2 U.S.C. § 441b (1976 ed.) (originally enacted as
the Federal Corrupt Practices Act, 34 Stat. 864), by their terms do
not apply to referendum votes. Several of the others proscribe or
limit spending for 'political' purposes, which may or may not cover
referenda.
See Schwartz v. Romnes, 495 F.2d 844 (CA2
1974)."
"The overriding concern behind the enactment of statutes such as
the Federal Corrupt Practices Act was the problem of corruption of
elected representatives through the creation of political debts.
See United States v. Automobile Workers, supra, at
352 U. S. 570-575;
Schwartz v. Romnes, supra, at 849-851. The importance of
the governmental interest in preventing this occurrence has never
been doubted. The case before us presents no comparable problem,
and our consideration of a corporation's right to speak on issues
of general public interest implies no comparable right in the quite
different context of participation in a political campaign for
election to public office. Congress might well be able to
demonstrate the existence of a danger of real or apparent
corruption in independent expenditures by corporations to influence
candidate elections.
Cf. Buckley v. Valeo; Comment, The
Regulation of Union Political Activity: Majority and Minority
Rights and Remedies, 126 U.Pa.L.Rev. 386, 408-410 (1977)."
First National Bank of Boston v. Bellotti, 435 U.S. at
435 U. S. 788,
n. 26.
Justice SCALIA, dissenting.
"Attention all citizens. To assure the fairness of elections by
preventing disproportionate expression of the views of any single
powerful group, your Government has decided that the following
associations of persons shall be prohibited from speaking or
writing in support of any candidate: _____"
In permitting Michigan to make private corporations the first
object of this Orwellian announcement, the Court today endorses the
principle that too much speech is an evil that the democratic
majority can proscribe. I dissent because that
Page 494 U. S. 680
principle is contrary to our case law and incompatible with the
absolutely central truth of the First Amendment: that government
cannot be trusted to assure, through censorship, the "fairness" of
political debate.
I
A
The Court's opinion says that political speech of corporations
can be regulated because "[s]tate law grants [them] special
advantages,"
ante at
494 U. S. 658,
and because this "unique state-conferred corporate structure . . .
facilitates the amassing of large treasuries."
Ante at
494 U. S. 660.
This analysis seeks to create one good argument by combining two
bad ones. Those individuals who form that type of voluntary
association known as a corporation are, to be sure, given special
advantages -- notably, the immunization of their personal fortunes
from liability for the actions of the association -- that the State
is under no obligation to confer. But so are other associations and
private individuals given all sorts of special advantages that the
State need not confer, ranging from tax breaks to contract awards
to public employment to outright cash subsidies. It is rudimentary
that the State cannot exact as the price of those special
advantages the forfeiture of First Amendment rights.
See
Pickering v. Board of Education, 391 U.
S. 563 (1968);
Speiser v. Randall, 357 U.
S. 513 (1958). The categorical suspension of the right
of any person, or of any association of persons, to speak out on
political matters must be justified by a compelling state need.
See Buckley v. Valeo, 424 U. S. 1,
424 U. S. 44-45
(1976) (per curiam). Which is why the Court puts forward its second
bad argument, the fact that corporations "amas[s] large
treasuries." But that alone is also not sufficient justification
for the suppression of political speech, unless one thinks it would
be lawful to prohibit men and women whose net worth is above a
certain figure from endorsing political candidates. Neither of
these two flawed arguments is
Page 494 U. S. 681
improved by combining them and saying, as the Court in effect
does, that
"since the State gives special advantages to these voluntary
associations, and since they thereby amass vast wealth, they may be
required to abandon their right of political speech."
The Court's extensive reliance upon the fact that the objects of
this speech restriction, corporations, receive "special advantages"
is in stark contrast to our opinion issued just six years ago in
FCC v. League of Women Voters of California, 468 U.
S. 364 (1984). In that decision, striking down a
congressionally imposed ban upon editorializing by noncommercial
broadcasting stations that receive federal funds, the
only
respect in which we considered the receipt of that "special
advantage" relevant was in determining whether the speech
limitation could be justified under Congress' spending power, as a
means of assuring that the subsidy was devoted only to the purposes
Congress intended, which did not include political editorializing.
We held it could not be justified on that basis, since
"a noncommercial educational station that receives only 1% of
its overall income from [federal] grants is barred absolutely from
all editorializing. . . . The station has
Page 494 U. S. 682
no way of limiting the use of its federal funds to all
noneditorializing activities, and, more importantly, it is barred
from using even wholly private funds to finance its editorial
activity."
Id. at
468 U. S. 400.
Of course the same is true here, even assuming that tax exemptions
and other benefits accorded to incorporated associations constitute
an exercise of the spending power. It is not just that portion of
the corporation's assets attributable to the gratuitously conferred
"special advantages" that is prohibited from being used for
political endorsements, but
all of the corporation's
assets. I am at a loss to explain the vast difference between the
treatment of the present case and
League of Women Voters.
Commercial corporations may not have a public persona as
sympathetic as that of public broadcasters, but they are no less
entitled to this Court's concern.
As for the second part of the Court's argumentation, the fact
that corporations (or at least some of them) possess "massive
wealth": Certain uses of "massive wealth" in the electoral process
-- whether or not the wealth is the result of "special advantages"
conferred by the State -- pose a substantial risk of corruption
which constitutes a compelling need for the regulation of speech.
Such a risk plainly exists when the wealth is given directly to the
political candidate, to be used under his direction and control. We
held in
Buckley v. Valeo, supra, however, that independent
expenditures to express the political views of individuals and
associations do not raise a sufficient threat of corruption to
justify prohibition.
Id. at
424 U. S. 45.
Neither the Court's opinion nor either of the concurrences makes
any effort to distinguish that case except, perhaps, by
misdescribing the case as involving "federal laws regulating
individual donors,"
ante at
494 U. S. 659,
or as involving "individual expenditures,"
ante at
494 U. S. 678
(STEVENS, J., concurring). Section 608(e)(1) of the Federal
Election Campaign Law, 18 U.S.C. § 608(e)(1) (1970 ed., Supp.
V), which we found unconstitutional in
Buckley, was
directed, like the Michigan law before us here, to expenditures
made for the purpose of advocating the election or defeat
Page 494 U. S. 683
of a particular candidate,
see 424 U.S. at
424 U. S. 42. It
limited to $1,000 (a lesser restriction than the absolute
prohibition at issue here) such expenditures not merely by
"individuals," but by "persons," specifically defined to include
corporations.
See id. at 187 (setting forth § 591(g)
of the statute). The plaintiffs in the case included corporations,
see id. at 8, and we specifically discussed §
608(e)(1) as a restriction addressed not just to individuals but to
"individuals and groups,"
id. at
424 U. S. 39,
424 U. S. 48,
"persons and groups,"
id. at 45, "persons and
organizations,"
ibid. "person[s] [and] association[s],"
id. at
424 U. S. 50. In
support of our determination that the restriction was "wholly at
odds with the guarantees of the First Amendment" we cited
Miami
Herald Publishing Co. v. Tornillo, 418 U.
S. 241 (1974), which involved limitations upon a
corporation. 424 U.S. at
424 U. S. 50. Of
course, if § 608(e)(1) had been unconstitutional only as
applied to individuals and not as applied to corporations, we might
nonetheless have invalidated it
in toto for substantial
overbreadth,
see Broadrick v. Oklahoma, 413 U.
S. 601,
413 U. S.
611-613 (1973), but there is not a hint of that doctrine
in our opinion. Our First Amendment law is much less certain than I
had thought it to be if we are free to recharacterize each clear
holding as a disguised "overbreadth" determination.
Buckley v. Valeo should not be overruled, because it is
entirely correct. The contention that prohibiting overt advocacy
for or against a political candidate satisfies a "compelling need"
to avoid "corruption" is easily dismissed. As we said in
Buckley,
"[i]t would naively underestimate the ingenuity and
resourcefulness of persons and groups desiring to buy influence to
believe that they would have much difficulty devising expenditures
that skirted the restriction on express advocacy of election or
defeat but nevertheless benefited the candidate's campaign."
424 U.S. at
424 U. S. 45.
Independent advocacy, moreover, unlike contributions, "may well
provide little assistance to the candidate's campaign and indeed
may prove counterproductive," thus reducing the danger that it will
be exchanged "as a
quid pro quo for improper
commitments
Page 494 U. S. 684
from the candidate."
Id. at
424 U. S. 47. The
latter point seems even more plainly true with respect to corporate
advocates than it is with respect to individuals. I expect I could
count on the fingers of one hand the candidates who would generally
welcome, much less negotiate for, a formal endorsement by AT &
T or General Motors. The advocacy of such entities that have
"amassed great wealth" will be effective only to the extent that it
brings to the people's attention
ideas which -- despite
the invariably self-interested and probably uncongenial source --
strike them as true.
The Court does not try to defend the proposition that
independent advocacy poses a substantial risk of political
"corruption," as English-speakers understand that term. Rather, it
asserts that that concept (which it defines as "
financial
quid pro quo' corruption," ante at 494 U. S. 659)
is really just a narrow subspecies of a hitherto unrecognized genus
of political corruption. "Michigan's regulation," we are
told,
"aims at a different type of corruption in the political arena:
the corrosive and distorting effects of immense aggregations of
wealth that are accumulated with the help of the corporate form and
that have little or no correlation to the public's support for the
corporations's political ideas."
Ibid. Under this mode of analysis, virtually anything
the Court deems politically undesirable can be turned into
political corruption -- by simply describing its effects as
politically "corrosive," which is close enough to "corruptive" to
qualify. It is sad to think that the First Amendment will
ultimately be brought down not by brute force but by poetic
metaphor.
The Court's opinion ultimately rests upon that proposition whose
violation constitutes the New Corruption: expenditures must
"reflect actual public support for the political ideas espoused."
Ante at
494 U. S. 660.
This illiberal free-speech principle of "one man, one minute" was
proposed and soundly rejected in
Buckley:
"It is argued, however, that the ancillary governmental interest
in equalizing the relative ability of individuals
Page 494 U. S. 685
and groups to influence the outcome of elections serves to
justify the limitation on express advocacy of the election or
defeat of candidates imposed by § 608(e)(1)'s expenditure
ceiling. But the concept that government may restrict the speech of
some elements of our society in order to enhance the relative voice
of others is wholly foreign to the First Amendment, which was
designed "to secure
the widest possible dissemination of
information from diverse and antagonistic sources,'" and "`to
assure unfettered interchange of ideas for the bringing about of
political and social changes desired by the people'""
424 U.S. at
424 U. S. 48-49
(citations omitted). But it can be said that I have not accurately
quoted today's decision. It does not endorse the proposition that
government may ensure that expenditures "reflect actual public
support for the political ideas espoused," but only the more
limited proposition that government may ensure that expenditures
"reflect actual public support for the political ideas espoused
by corporations."
Ante at
494 U. S. 660
(emphasis added). The limitation is of course entirely irrational.
Why is it perfectly all right if advocacy by an individual
billionaire is out of proportion with "actual public support" for
his positions? There is no explanation, except the effort I
described at the outset of this discussion to make one valid
proposition out of two invalid ones: When the vessel labeled
"corruption" begins to founder under weight too great to be
logically sustained, the argumentation jumps to the good ship
"special privilege"; and when that in turn begins to go down, it
returns to "corruption." Thus hopping back and forth between the
two, the argumentation may survive, but makes no headway towards
port, where its conclusion waits in vain.
B
Justice BRENNAN's concurrence would have us believe that the
prohibition adopted by Michigan and approved by the Court is a
paternalistic measure to protect the corporate
Page 494 U. S. 686
shareholder of America. It is designed, we are told, "to avert
[the] danger" that "corporate funds drawn from the general treasury
-- which represents, after all, [the shareholder's] money," might
be used on behalf of a political candidate he opposes.
Ante at
494 U. S. 670
(BRENNAN, J., concurring). But such solicitude is a most
implausible explanation for the Michigan statute, inasmuch as it
permits corporations to take as many ideological and political
positions as they please, so long as they are not "in assistance
of, or in opposition to, the nomination or election of a
candidate." Mich. Comp. Laws § 169.206(1) (1979). That is
indeed the Court's sole basis for distinguishing
First National
Bank of Boston v. Bellotti, 435 U. S. 765
(1978), which invalidated restriction of a corporation's general
political speech. The Michigan law appears to be designed, in other
words, neither to protect shareholders, nor even (impermissibly) to
"balance" general political debate, but to protect political
candidates. Given the degree of political sophistication that ought
to attend the exercise of our constitutional responsibilities, it
is regrettable that this should come as a surprise.
But even if the object of the prohibition could plausibly be
portrayed as the protection of shareholders (which the Court's
opinion, at least, does not even assert), that would not suffice as
a "compelling need" to support this blatant restriction upon core
political speech. A person becomes a member of that form of
association known as a for-profit corporation in order to pursue
economic objectives,
i.e., to make money. Some corporate
charters may specify the line of commerce to which the company is
limited, but even that can be amended by shareholder vote. Thus, in
joining such an association, the shareholder knows that management
may take any action that is ultimately in accord with what the
majority (or a specified supermajority) of the shareholders wishes,
so long as that action is designed to make a profit. That is the
deal. The corporate actions to which the shareholder exposes
himself, therefore, include many things that
Page 494 U. S. 687
he may find politically or ideologically uncongenial: investment
in South Africa, operation of an abortion clinic, publication of a
pornographic magazine, or even publication of a newspaper that
adopts absurd political views and makes catastrophic political
endorsements. His only protections against such assaults upon his
ideological commitments are (1) his ability to persuade a majority
(or the requisite minority) of his fellow shareholders that the
action should not be taken, and ultimately (2) his ability to sell
his stock. (The latter course, by the way, does not ordinarily
involve the severe psychic trauma or economic disaster that Justice
BRENNAN's opinion suggests.) It seems to me entirely fanciful, in
other words, to suggest that the Michigan statute makes any
significant contribution towards insulating the exclusively
profit-motivated shareholder from the rude world of politics and
ideology.
But even if that were not fanciful, it would be fanciful to
think, as Justice BRENNAN's opinion assumes, that there is any
difference between for-profit and not-for-profit corporations
insofar as the need for protection of the individual member's
ideological psyche is concerned. Would it be any more upsetting to
a shareholder of General Motors that it endorsed the election of
Henry Wallace (to stay comfortably in the past) than it would be to
a member of the American Civil Liberties Union that it endorsed the
election of George Wallace? I should think much less so. Yet in the
one case as in the other, the only protection against
association-induced trauma is the will of the majority and, in the
last analysis, withdrawal from membership.
C
In Part V of its opinion, the Court accurately sets forth our
long-standing First Amendment law as follows:
"Because the right to engage in political expression is
fundamental to our constitutional system, statutory classifications
impinging upon that right must be narrowly
Page 494 U. S. 688
tailored to serve a compelling governmental interest."
Ante at
494 U. S. 666.
The Court finds this requirement fully met for the following
reason:
"As we explained in the context of our discussions of whether
the statute was overinclusive,
supra at
494 U. S.
660-661, or under-inclusive,
supra at
494 U. S. 665 and this page,
the State's decision to regulate only corporations is precisely
tailored to serve the compelling state interest of eliminating from
the political process the corrosive effect of political 'war
chests' amassed with the aid of the legal advantages given to
corporations."
Ibid. That state interest (assuming it is compelling)
does indeed explain why the State chose to silence "only
corporations" rather than wealthy individuals as well. But it does
not explain (what "narrow tailoring" pertains to) why the State
chose to silence
all corporations, rather than just those
that possess great wealth. If narrow tailoring means anything,
surely it must mean that action taken to counter the effect of
amassed "war chests" must be targeted, if possible, at amassed "war
chests." And surely such targeting is possible -- either in the
manner accomplished by the provision that we invalidated in
Buckley, i.e., by limiting the prohibition to independent
expenditures above a certain amount, or in some other manner,
e.g., by limiting the expenditures of only those
corporations with more than a certain amount of net worth or annual
profit.
No more satisfactory explanation for the obvious lack of "narrow
tailoring" is to be found in the Court's discussion of
overinclusiveness, to which the above quoted passage refers. That
discussion asserts that we "rejected a similar argument" in
FEC
v. National Right to Work Comm., 459 U.
S. 197 (1982) (
NRWC), where we said that "we
accept Congress' judgment" that "the special characteristics of the
corporate structure" create a "
potential for . . .
influence that demands
Page 494 U. S. 689
regulation."
Ante at
494 U. S. 661,
quoting 459 U.S. at
459 U. S.
209-210 (emphasis added by the Court). Today's opinion
then continues:
"Although some closely held corporations, just as some publicly
held ones, may not have accumulated significant amounts of wealth,
they receive from the State the special benefits conferred by the
corporate structure and present the potential for distorting the
political process. This potential for distortion justifies §
54(1)'s general applicability to all corporations."
Ante at
494 U. S.
661.
The Court thus holds, for the first time since Justice Holmes
left the bench, that a direct restriction upon speech is narrowly
enough tailored if it extends to speech that has the mere
potential for producing social harm.
FEC v. National
Right to Work Committee (which in any event involved not a
direct restriction upon corporate speech but a restriction upon
corporate solicitation of funds for candidates) is no authority for
that startling proposition, since it
did not purport to be
applying the First Amendment narrow-tailoring requirement. The
principle the court abandons today -- that the mere potential for
harm does not justify a restriction upon speech -- had its origin
in the "clear and present danger" test devised by Justice Holmes in
1919,
see Schenck v. United States, 249 U. S.
47,
249 U. S. 49-51,
and championed by him and Justice Brandeis over the next decade in
a series of famous opinions opposing the affirmance of convictions
for subversive speech,
see Abrams v. United States,
250 U. S. 616
(1919) (Holmes, J., dissenting);
Gitlow v. New York,
268 U. S. 652,
268 U. S. 672
(1925) (Holmes, J., dissenting);
Whitney v. California,
274 U. S. 357,
274 U. S. 374
(1919) (Brandeis, J., concurring). The Court finally adopted their
view in 1937,
see Herndon v. Lowry, 301 U.
S. 242,
301 U. S. 258;
see also Bridges v. California, 314 U.
S. 252,
314 U. S. 263
(1941);
Thornhill v. Alabama, 310 U. S.
88,
310 U. S. 105
(1940);
West Virginia Board of Education v. Barnette,
319 U. S. 624,
319 U. S. 639
(1943);
Terminiello v. Chicago, 337 U. S.
1,
337 U. S. 4-5
(1949). Today's reversal of field will require adjustment of a
fairly large number of significant First Amendment holdings.
Presumably the State
Page 494 U. S. 690
may now convict individuals for selling books found to have a
potentially harmful influence on minors,
Butler v.
Michigan, 352 U. S. 380
(1957), ban indecent telephone communications that have the
potential of reaching minors,
Sable Communications of
California v. FCC, 492 U. S. 115
(1989), restrain the press from publishing information that has the
potential of jeopardizing a criminal defendant's right to a fair
trial,
Nebraska Press Assn. v. Stuart, 427 U.
S. 539 (1976), or the potential of damaging the
reputation of the subject of an investigation,
Communications,
Inc. v. Virginia, 435 U. S. 829
(1978), compel publication of the membership lists of organizations
that have a potential for illegal activity,
see NAACP v.
Alabama ex rel. Patterson, 357 U. S. 449,
357 U. S. 464
(1958), and compel an applicant for bar membership to reveal her
political beliefs and affiliations to eliminate the potential for
subversive activity,
Baird v. State Bar of Arizona,
401 U. S. 1
(1971).
It is perplexing, or perhaps revealing, to compare the Court's
cavalier treatment of the narrow tailoring requirement today with
its elaborate discussion of that issue six years ago in
League
of Women Voters. See 468 U.S. at
469 U. S.
392-395,
468 U. S.
397-398. As my earlier discussion makes clear, it would
make no difference if the law
were narrowly tailored to
serve its goal, since that goal is not compelling. But the fact
that, even having made that first error, the Court must make yet a
second in order to reach today's judgment suggests what an
impregnable fortress out First Amendment jurisprudence has been.
The Court's explicit acceptance of "potential danger" as adequate
to establish narrow tailoring, even more than its recognition of an
insubstantial interests as "compelling," greatly weakens those
defenses.
D
Finally, a few words are in order concerning the Court's
approval of the Michigan law's exception for "media corporations."
This is all right, we are told, because of "the unique
Page 494 U. S. 691
role that the press plays in
informing and educating the
public, offering criticism, and providing a forum for discussion
and debate.'" Ante at 494 U. S. 667
(citation omitted). But if one believes in the Court's rationale of
"compelling state need" to prevent amassed corporate wealth from
skewing the political debate, surely that "unique role" of the
press does not give Michigan justification for excluding
media corporations from coverage, but provides especially strong
reason to include them. Amassed corporate wealth that
regularly sits astride the ordinary channels of information is much
more likely to produce the New Corruption (too much of one point of
view) than amassed corporate wealth that is generally busy making
money elsewhere. Such media corporations not only have vastly
greater power to perpetrate the evil of overinforming, they also
have vastly greater opportunity. General Motors, after all, will
risk a stockholder suit if it makes a political endorsement that is
not plausibly tied to its ability to make money for its
shareholders. But media corporations make money by making
political commentary, including endorsements. For them, unlike any
other corporations, the whole world of politics and ideology is
fair game. Yet the Court tells us that it is reasonable to
exclude media corporations, rather than target them
specially.
Members of the institutional press, despite the Court's approval
of their illogical exemption from the Michigan law, will find
little reason for comfort in today's decision. The theory of New
Corruption it espouses is a dagger at their throat. The Court today
holds merely that media corporations may be excluded from the
Michigan law, not that they
must be. We have consistently
rejected the proposition that the institutional press has any
constitutional privilege beyond that of other speakers.
See
Bellotti, 435 U.S. at
435 U. S. 782, and cases cited. Thus, the Court's
holding on this point must be put in the following unencouraging
form:
"Although the press' unique societal role may not entitle the
press to greater protection under the Constitution,
Bellotti,
supra, at
435 U. S. 782, and
Page 494 U. S. 692
n. 18, it does provide a compelling reason for the State to
exempt media corporations from the scope of political expenditure
limitations."
Ante at
494 U. S. 668.
One must hope, I suppose, that Michigan will continue to provide
this generous and voluntary exemption.
II
I would not do justice to the significance of today's decision
to discuss only its lapses from case precedent and logic.
Infinitely more important than that is its departure from long
accepted premises of our political system regarding the benevolence
that can be expected of government in managing the arena of public
debate, and the danger that is to be anticipated from powerful
private institutions that compete with government, and with one
another, within that arena.
Perhaps the Michigan law before us here has an unqualifiedly
noble objective -- to "equalize" the political debate by preventing
disproportionate expression of corporations' points of view. But
governmental abridgement of liberty is always undertaken with the
very best of announced objectives (dictators promise to bring
order, not tyranny), and often with the very best of genuinely
intended objectives (zealous policemen conduct unlawful searches in
order to put dangerous felons behind bars). The premise of our Bill
of Rights, however, is that there are some things -- even some
seemingly
desirable things -- that government cannot be
trusted to do. The very first of these is establishing the
restrictions upon speech that will assure "fair" political debate.
The incumbent politician who says he welcomes full and fair debate
is no more to be believed than the entrenched monopolist who says
he welcomes full and fair competition. Perhaps the Michigan
legislature was genuinely trying to assure a "balanced"
presentation of political views; on the other hand, perhaps it was
trying to give unincorporated unions (a not insubstantial force in
Michigan) political advantage over major employers. Or perhaps it
was trying to assure a "balanced" presentation because it knows
that, with evenly balanced
Page 494 U. S. 693
speech, incumbent officeholders generally win. The fundamental
approach of the First Amendment, I had always thought, was to
assume the worst, and to rule the regulation of political speech
"for fairness' sake" simply out of bounds.
I doubt that those who framed and adopted the First Amendment
would agree that avoiding the New Corruption, that is, calibrating
political speech to the degree of public opinion that supports it,
is even a
desirable objective, much less one that is
important enough to qualify as a compelling state interest. Those
Founders designed, of course, a system in which popular ideas would
ultimately prevail; but also, through the First Amendment, a system
in which true ideas could readily become popular. For the latter
purpose, the calibration that the Court today endorses is precisely
backwards: To the extent a valid proposition has scant public
support, it should have wider, rather than narrower, public
circulation. I am confident, in other words, that Jefferson and
Madison would not have sat at these controls; but if they did, they
would have turned them in the opposite direction.
Ah, but then there is the special element of corporate wealth:
What would the Founders have thought of that? They would have
endorsed, I think, what Tocqueville wrote in 1835:
"When the members of an aristocratic community adopt a new
opinion or conceive a new sentiment, they give it a station, as it
were, beside themselves, upon the lofty platform where they stand;
and opinions or sentiments so conspicuous to the eyes of the
multitude are easily introduced into the minds or hearts of all
around. In democratic countries the governing power alone is
naturally in a condition to act in this manner; but it is easy to
see that its action is always inadequate, and often dangerous. . .
. No sooner does a government attempt to go beyond its political
sphere and to enter upon this new track than it exercises, even
unintentionally, an insupportable tyranny. . . . Worse still will
be the case if the
Page 494 U. S. 694
government really believes itself interested in preventing all
circulation of ideas; it will then stand motionless and oppressed
by the heaviness of voluntary torpor. Governments, therefore,
should not be the only active powers; associations ought, in
democratic nations, to stand in lieu of those powerful private
individuals whom the equality of conditions has swept away."
2 A. de Tocqueville, Democracy in America 109 (Bradley ed. 1948)
While Tocqueville was discussing "circulation of ideas" in general,
what he wrote is also true of candidate endorsements in particular.
To eliminate voluntary associations -- not only including powerful
ones, but
especially including powerful ones -- from the
public debate is either to augment the always dominant power of
government or to impoverish the public debate. The case at hand is
a good enough example. Why should Michigan voters in the 93d House
District be deprived of the information that private associations
owning and operating a vast percentage of the industry of the
State, and employing a large number of its citizens, believe that
the election of a particular candidate is important to their
prosperity? Contrary to the Court's suggestion, the same point
cannot effectively be made through corporate PACs to which
individuals may voluntarily contribute. It is important to the
message that it represents the views of Michigan's leading
corporations
as corporations, occupying the "lofty
platform" that they do within the economic life of the State -- not
just the views of some
other voluntary associations to
which some of the corporations' shareholders belong.
Despite all the talk about "corruption and the appearance of
corruption" -- evils that are not significantly implicated and that
can be avoided in many other ways -- it is entirely obvious that
the object of the law we have approved today is not to prevent
wrongdoing, but to prevent speech. Since those
Page 494 U. S. 695
private associations known as corporations have so much money,
they will speak so much more, and their views will be given
inordinate prominence in election campaigns. This is not an
argument that our democratic traditions allow -- neither with
respect to individuals associated in corporations nor with respect
to other categories of individuals whose speech may be "unduly"
extensive (because they are rich) or "unduly" persuasive (because
they are movie stars) or "unduly" respected (because they are
clergymen). The premise of our system is that there is no such
thing as too much speech -- that the people are not foolish, but
intelligent, and will separate the wheat from the chaff. As
conceded in Lincoln's aphorism about fooling "all of the people
some of the time," that premise will not invariably accord with
reality; but it will assuredly do so much more frequently than the
premise the Court today embraces: that a health democratic system
can survive the legislative power to prescribe how much political
speech is too much, who may speak, and who may not.
* * * *
Because today's decision is inconsistent with unrepudiated legal
judgments of our Court, but even more because it is incompatible
with the unrepealable political wisdom of our First Amendment, I
dissent.
* The Court's assertion that the Michigan law "does not impose
an
absolute ban on all forms of corporate political
spending,"
ante at
494 U. S. 660
(emphasis added), is true only in a respect that is irrelevant for
purposes of First Amendment analysis. A corporation is absolutely
prohibited from spending its own funds on this form of political
speech, and would be guilty of misrepresentation if it asserted
that a particular candidate was supported or opposed by the
corporation. This is to say that the corporation
as a
corporation is prohibited from speaking. What the Michigan law
permits the corporation to do is to serve as the founder and
treasurer of a different association of individuals that can
endorse or oppose political candidates. The equivalent, where an
individual rather an association is concerned, would be to prohibit
John D. Rockefeller from making political endorsements, but to
permit him to form an association to which others (though not he
himself) can contribute for the purpose of making political
endorsements. Just as political speech by that association is not
speech by John D. Rockefeller, so also speech by a corporate PAC
that the Michigan law allows is not speech by the corporation
itself.
Justice KENNEDY, with whom Justice O'CONNOR and Justice SCALIA
join, dissenting.
The majority opinion validates not one censorship of speech, but
two. One is Michigan's content-based law which decrees it a crime
for a nonprofit corporate speaker to endorse or oppose candidates
for Michigan public office. By permitting the statute to stand, the
Court upholds a direct restriction on the independent expenditure
of funds for political speech for the first time in its
history.
The other censorship scheme, I most regret to say, is of our own
creation. It is value-laden, content-based speech
Page 494 U. S. 696
suppression that permits some nonprofit corporate groups, but
not of hers, to engage in political speech. After failing to
disguise its animosity and distrust for the particular kind of
political speech here at issue -- the qualifications of a candidate
to understand economic matters -- the Court adopts a rule that
allows Michigan to stifle the voices of some of the most respected
groups in public life on subjects central to the integrity of our
democratic system. Each of these schemes is repugnant to the First
Amendment and contradicts its central guarantee, the freedom to
speak in the electoral process. I dissent.
I
To understand the force of the Michigan statutory censorship
scheme, one need not go beyond the facts of the case before us. The
Michigan Chamber of Commerce is a nonprofit corporation with an
interest in candidates and public policy issues throughout the
State of Michigan. The Chamber sought, on its own initiative and
without communication with the candidate, to place a newspaper
advertisement in support of one Richard Bandstra, a candidate for
the House of Representatives in Michigan. (The proposed
advertisement is reproduced in the Appendix to this opinion.
[Appendix omitted from this electronic version.]) The advertisement
discussed the local economy and unemployment and explained why the
candidate supported by the Chamber would understand and improve
local economic conditions. This communication is banned by the law
here in question, the Michigan Campaign Finance Act (Act), 1976
Mich.Pub. Acts 388, Mich.Comp. Laws § 169.201
et seq.
(1979).
The Act prohibits "a corporation," including a non-profit
corporation, from making any "expenditure" in connection with an
election campaign for state office. [
Footnote 3/1] An expenditure
Page 494 U. S. 697
includes any payment or other contribution in "assistance of, or
in opposition to, the nomination or election of a candidate. . . ."
[
Footnote 3/2] The Act by its terms
forbids corporations from making "independent expenditures"
undertaken without any coordination or even communication with a
candidate's organization. [
Footnote
3/3] Under the Act, a corporate expenditure made for
Page 494 U. S. 698
purposes of communicating on issues of public policy is
permissible only if it does not support or oppose a candidate by
name or by "inference." [
Footnote
3/4] Violation of the Act is a felony. [
Footnote 3/5]
A
The State has conceded that among those communications
prohibited by its statute are the publication by a nonprofit
corporation of its own assessment of a candidate's voting record.
With the imprimatur of this Court, it is now a felony in Michigan
for the Sierra Club, or the American Civil Liberties Union, or the
Michigan State Chamber of Commerce, to advise the public how a
candidate voted on issues of urgent concern to their members. In
both practice and theory, the prohibition aims at the heart of
political debate.
As the majority must acknowledge, and as no party contests, the
advertisement in this case is a paradigm of political speech.
Buckley v. Valeo, 424 U. S. 1,
424 U. S. 14-15
(1976). The Michigan statute bans it, however, along with all other
communications by nonprofit corporate speakers that carry an
inference of support for or opposition to a candidate, on the sole
ground that the speaker is organized in corporate form. The Act
operates to prohibit information essential to the ability of voters
to evaluate candidates. In my view, this speech cannot be
restricted.
Far more than the interest of the Chamber is at stake. We
confront here society's interest in free and informed discussion on
political issues, a discourse vital to the capacity for
self-government.
"In the realm of protected speech, the legislature is
constitutionally disqualified from dictating the subjects about
which persons may speak and the speakers who
Page 494 U. S. 699
may address a public issue."
First National Bank of Boston v. Bellotti, 435 U.
S. 765,
435 U. S.
784-785 (1978). There is little doubt that, by silencing
advocacy groups that operate in the corporate form and forbidding
them to speak on electoral politics, Michigan's law suffers from
both of these constitutional defects.
First, the Act prohibits corporations from speaking on a
particular subject, the subject of candidate elections. It is a
basic precept that the State may not confine speech to certain
subjects. Content-based restrictions are the essence of censorial
power.
Id. at
435 U. S.
784-785 (invalidating statute that allowed corporations
to speak on referenda issues that materially affected their
business, but not on other subjects).
See also Consolidated
Edison Co. of New York v. Public Service Comm'n of New York,
447 U. S. 530,
447 U. S. 537
(1980) ("The First Amendment's hostility to content-based
regulation extends not only to restrictions on particular
viewpoints, but also to prohibition of public discussion of an
entire topic").
Second, the Act discriminates on the basis of the speaker's
identity. Under the Michigan law, any person or group other than a
corporation may engage in political debate over candidate
elections; but corporations, even nonprofit corporations that have
unique views of vital importance to the electorate, must remain
mute. Out precedents condemn this censorship.
See Bellotti,
supra, at
435 U. S.
784-786;
Police Dept. of Chicago v. Mosley,
408 U. S. 92 (1972)
(invalidating state statute that prohibited picketing near certain
buildings but allowed certain labor picketers);
Carey v.
Brown, 447 U. S. 455
(1980).
The protection afforded core political speech is not diminished
because the speaker is a nonprofit corporation. Even in the case of
a for-profit corporation, we have upheld the right to speak on
ballot issues. The
Bellotti Court stated:
"If the speakers here were not corporations, no one would
suggest that the State could silence their proposed speech. It is
the type of speech indispensable to decisionmaking
Page 494 U. S. 700
in a democracy, and this is no less true because the speech
comes from a corporation rather than an individual. The inherent
worth of the speech in terms of its capacity for informing the
public does not depend upon the identity of its source, whether
corporation, association, union, or individual."
435 U.S. at
435 U. S. 777
(footnotes omitted).
By using distinctions based upon both the speech and the
speaker, the Act engages in the rawest form of censorship: the
State censors what a particular segment of the political community
might say with regard to candidates who stand for election. The
Court's holding cannot be reconciled with the principle that
"'legislative restrictions on advocacy of the election or defeat
of political candidates are wholly at odds with the guarantees of
the First Amendment.'"
Meyer v. Grant, 486 U. S. 414,
486 U. S. 428
(1988), quoting
Buckley v. Valeo, 424 U.S. at
424 U. S. 50.
B
The second censorship scheme validated by today's holding is the
one imposed by the Court. In
FEC v. Massachusetts Citizens for
Life, Inc., 479 U. S. 238
(1986) (
MCFL ), a First Amendment right to use corporate
treasury funds was recognized for the nonprofit corporation then
before us. Those who thought that the First Amendment exists to
protect all points of view in candidate elections will be
disillusioned by the Court's opinion today, for that protection is
given only to a preferred class of nonprofit corporate speakers:
small, single issue nonprofit corporations that pass the Court's
own vague test for determining who are the favored participants in
the electoral process. There can be no doubt that, if a State were
to enact a statute empowering an administrative board to determine
which corporations could place candidate advertisements in
newspapers and which could not, with authority to enforce the
guidelines the Court adopts today to distinguish between the
Massachusetts Citizens for Life and the Michigan Chamber of
Commerce, the statute would be
Page 494 U. S. 701
held unconstitutional. The First Amendment does not permit
courts to exercise speech suppression authority denied to
legislatures.
The Court draws support for its discrimination among nonprofit
corporate speakers from portions of our opinion in
MCFL,
supra. It must be acknowledged that certain language in
MCFL, in particular the discussion which pointed to the
express purpose of the organization to promote political ideas,
id. at
479 U. S.
263-265, lends support to the majority's test. That
language, however, contravenes fundamental principles of neutrality
for all political speech. It should not stand in the way of giving
full force to the essential and vital holding of
MCFL,
which is that a nonprofit corporation engaged in political
discussion of candidates and elections has the full protection of
the First Amendment.
II
The Act does not meet our standards for laws that burden
fundamental rights. The State cannot demonstrate that a compelling
interest supports its speech restriction, nor can it show that its
law is narrowly tailored to the purported statutory end.
See
Bellotti, 435 U.S. at
435 U. S. 786,
435 U. S.
793-795. Restrictions on independent expenditures are
unconstitutional if they fail to meet both of these standards.
Buckley v. Valeo, 424 U. S. 1 (1976);
First National Bank of Boston v. Bellotti, supra; FEC v.
National Conservative Political Action Committee, 470 U.
S. 480 (1985) (
NCPAC);
MCFL, supra.
The majority opinion cannot establish either of these predicate
conditions for the speech restriction imposed by the State.
[
Footnote 3/6]
Page 494 U. S. 702
Our cases acknowledge the danger that corruption poses for the
electoral process, but draw a line in permissible regulation
between payments to candidates ("contributions") and payments or
expenditures to express one's own views ("independent
expenditures"). Today's decision abandons this distinction and
threatens once protected political speech. The Michigan statute
prohibits independent expenditures by a nonprofit corporate speaker
to express its own views about candidate qualifications.
Independent expenditures are entitled to greater protection than
campaign contributions.
MCFL, supra, 479 U.S. at
479 U. S.
259-260.
See also Buckley, 424 U.S. at
424 U. S.
20-21.
"[E]xpenditure ceilings impose significantly more severe
restrictions on protected freedoms of political expression and
association than do . . . limitations on financial
contributions."
Id. at
424 U. S. 23.
Candidate campaign contributions are subject to greater regulation
because of the enhanced risk of corruption from the possibility
that a large contribution would be given to secure political
favors; independent expenditures pose no such risk:
"Unlike contributions, such independent expenditures may well
provide little assistance to the candidate's campaign and indeed
may prove counterproductive. The absence of prearrangement and
coordination of an expenditure with the candidate or his agent not
only undermines the value of the expenditure to the candidate, but
also alleviates the danger that expenditures will be given as a
quid pro quo for improper commitments from the
candidate."
Id. at
424 U. S. 47.
Appellant's reliance on cases involving contributions, such as
FEC v. National Right to Work Committee, 459 U.
S. 197 (1982), is misplaced.
The proper analysis must follow our cases on independent
expenditures. We have established that limitations on
independent
Page 494 U. S. 703
political expenditures are subject to exacting First Amendment
scrutiny. In
Buckley, we invalidated a federal limitation
on independent expenditures because they had no tendency to
corrupt. By like analysis, we invalidated a ban on independent
corporate expenditures for referenda issues,
First National
Bank of Boston v. Bellotti, supra, and a federal limitation
which prohibited political committees from spending more than
$1,000 in support of any candidate who had accepted public funding,
NCPAC, 470 U.S. at
470 U. S. 491.
In
NCPAC, we found that the mere hypothetical possibility
that candidates may take notice of and reward PAC expenditures by
giving official favors was insufficient to demonstrate that the
threat of corruption justified the spending regulation.
Id. at
470 U. S.
497.
The majority almost admits that, in the case of independent
expenditures, the danger of a political
quid pro quo is
insufficient to justify a restriction of this kind. Since the
specter of corruption, which had been "the only legitimate and
compelling government interest[s] thus far identified for
restricting campaign finances,"
NCPAC, supra, at
470 U. S.
496-497, is missing in this case, the majority invents a
new interest: combatting the "corrosive and distorting effects of
immense aggregations of wealth,"
ante at
494 U. S. 660,
accumulated in corporate form without shareholder or public
support. The majority styles this novel interest as simply a
different kind of corruption, but has no support for its assertion.
While it is questionable whether such imprecision would suffice to
justify restricting political speech by for-profit corporations, it
is certain that it does not apply to nonprofit entities.
The evil of political corruption has been defined in more
precise terms. We have said: "Corruption is a subversion of the
political process" whereby "[e]lected officials are influenced to
act contrary to their obligations of office by the prospect of
financial gain. . . . "
NCPAC, supra, at
470 U. S. 497.
In contrast, the interest touted by the majority is the
impermissible
Page 494 U. S. 704
one of altering political debate by muting the impact of certain
speakers.
The regulatory mechanism adopted by the Michigan statute is
aimed at reducing the quantity of political speech, a rationale
endorsed by today's majority. The First Amendment rests on quite
the opposite theory. As we have already said in the context of
political expenditures:
"A restriction on the amount of money a person or group can
spend on political communication during a campaign necessarily
reduces the quantity of expression by restricting the number of
issues discussed, the depth of their exploration, and the size of
the audience reached. This is because virtually every means of
communicating ideas in today's mass society requires the
expenditure of money."
Buckley, 424 U.S. at
424 U. S. 19
(footnote omitted);
see also id. at
424 U. S. 39.
In
Buckley and Bellotti, acting on these precepts, we
rejected the argument that the expenditure of money to increase the
quantity of political speech somehow fosters corruption. The key to
the majority's reasoning appears to be that, because some corporate
speakers are well-supported and can buy press space or broadcast
time to express their ideas, government may ban all corporate
speech to ensure that it will not dominate political debate. The
argument is flawed in at least two respects. First, the statute is
overinclusive, because it covers all groups which use the corporate
form, including all nonprofit corporations. Second, it assumes that
the government has a legitimate interest in equalizing the relative
influence of speakers.
With regard to nonprofit corporations in particular, there is no
reason to assume that the corporate form has an intrinsic flaw that
makes it corrupt, or that all corporations possess great wealth, or
that all corporations can buy more media coverage for their views
than can individuals or other groups. There is no reason to
conclude that independent speech by
Page 494 U. S. 705
a corporation is any more likely to dominate the political arena
than speech by the wealthy individual, protected in
Buckley v.
Valeo, supra, or by the well-funded PAC, protected in
NCPAC, supra, (protecting speech rights of PAC's against
expenditure limitations). In
NCPAC, we discredited the
argument that, because PAC's spend larger amounts than individuals,
the potential for corruption is greater.
Id. at
470 U. S.
497-498. We distinguished between the campaign
contribution at issue in
FEC v. National Right to Work
Committee, supra, and independent expenditures, by noting
that, while
"the compelling govern mental interest in preventing corruption
supported the restriction of the influence of political war chests
funneled through the corporate form"
with regard to candidate campaign contributions, a similar
finding could not be supported for independent expenditures.
NCPAC, supra, 470 U.S. at
470 U. S.
500-501.
In addition, the notion that the government has a legitimate
interest in restricting the quantity of speech to equalize the
relative influence of speakers on elections is antithetical to the
First Amendment:
"[T]he concept that government may restrict the speech of some
elements of our society in order to enhance the relative voice of
others is wholly foreign to the First Amendment, which was designed
"to secure
the widest possible dissemination of information
from diverse and antagonistic sources,'". . . The First Amendment's
protection against governmental abridgment of free expression
cannot properly be made to depend on a person's financial ability
to engage in public discussion."
Buckley, 424 U.S. at
424 U. S. 48-49
(citations omitted).
That those who can afford to publicize their views may succeed
in the political arena as a result does not detract from the fact
that they are exercising a First Amendment right.
Meyer v.
Grant, 486 U.S. at
486 U. S. 426,
n. 7 (upholding First Amendment right to use paid petition
circulators). As we
Page 494 U. S. 706
stated in
Bellotti, paid advocacy
"may influence the outcome of the vote; this would be its
purpose. But the fact that advocacy may persuade the electorate is
hardly a reason to suppress it."
435 U.S. at
435 U. S. 790.
The suggestion that the government has an interest in shaping the
political debate by insulating the electorate from too much
exposure to certain views is incompatible with the First
Amendment.
"[T]he people in our democracy are entrusted with the
responsibility for judging and evaluating the relative merits of
conflicting arguments."
Id. at
435 U. S. 791;
see alsoMeyer, supra, at
486 U. S. 426,
n. 7;
Brown v. Hartlage, 456 U. S. 45,
456 U. S. 60
(1982).
A similar argument to that made by the majority was rejected in
Bellotti. There, we rejected the assumption that
"corporations are wealthy and powerful and their views may drown
out other points of view" or "exert an undue influence" on the
electorate in the absence of a showing that the relative voice of
corporations was significant. 435 U.S. at
435 U. S. 789.
And even were we to assume that some record support for this
assertion would make a constitutional difference, it has not been
established here. The majority provides only conjecture. All
censorship is suspect, but censorship based on vague surmise is not
permissible in any case.
The Act, as the State itself says, prevents a nonprofit
corporate speaker from using its own funds to inform the voting
public that a particular candidate has a good or bad voting record
on issues of interest to the association's adherents. Though our
era may not be alone in deploring the lack of mechanisms for
holding candidates accountable for the votes they cast, that lack
of accountability is one of the major concerns of our time. The
speech suppressed in this case was directed to political
qualifications. The fact that it was spoken by the Michigan Chamber
of Commerce, and not a man or woman standing on a soapbox, detracts
not a scintilla from its validity, its persuasiveness, or its
contribution to the political dialogue.
Page 494 U. S. 707
The Court purports to distinguish
MCFL on the ground
that the nonprofit corporation permitted to speak in that case
received no funds from profit-making corporations. It is undisputed
that the Michigan Chamber of Commerce is itself a nonprofit
corporation. The crucial difference, it is said, is that the
Chamber receives corporate contributions. But this distinction
rests on the fallacy that the source of the speaker's funds is
somehow relevant to the speaker's right of expression or society's
interest in hearing what the speaker has to say. There is no reason
that the free speech rights of an individual or of an association
of individuals should turn on the circumstance that funds used to
engage in the speech come from a corporation. Many persons can
trace their funds to corporations, if not in the form of donations,
then in the form of dividends, interest, or salary. That does not
provide a basis to deprive such individuals or associations of
their First Amendment freedoms. The more narrow alternative of
recordkeeping and funding disclosure is available.
See
MCFL, 479 U.S. at
479 U. S. 262.
A wooden rule prohibiting independent expenditures by nonprofit
corporations that receive funds from business corporations invites
discriminatory distinctions. The principled approach is to
acknowledge that, where political speech is concerned, freedom to
speak extends to all nonprofit corporations, not the special
favorites of a majority of this Court.
B
The majority concludes that the Michigan Act is narrowly
tailored. First, it seeks support in the availability of political
action committees (PAC's) as an alternative to direct speech.
Second, the majority advances the rationale that the restriction
protects shareholders from the use of corporate funds to support
speech with which they may not agree. Third, it asserts that
independent expenditures funded by corporate wealth pose inherent
dangers. None of these justifications can suffice to save the
Act.
Page 494 U. S. 708
That the censorship applies to the nonprofit corporate speaker
itself, and not to a PAC that it has organized, far from being a
saving feature of the regulation, further condemns it. The argument
that the availability of a PAC as an alternate means,
see
Mich.Comp. Laws § 169.255 (1979), can save a restriction on
independent corporate expenditures was rejected by the Court in
MCFL, supra, at
479 U. S.
253-255;
id. at
479 U. S. 266
(O'CONNOR, J., concurring), as a costly and burdensome disincentive
to speech. The record in this case tended to show that between 25
and 50 percent of a PAC's funds are required to establish and
administer the PAC.
See App. 103a, 108a. While the
corporation can direct the PAC to make expenditures on behalf of
candidates, the PAC can be funded only by contributions from
shareholders, directors, officers, and managerial employees, and
cannot receive corporate treasury funds. Mich.Comp. Laws §
169.255(3) (1979). That the avenue left open is more burdensome
than the one foreclosed is "sufficient to characterize [a statute]
as an infringement on First Amendment activities." 479 U.S. at
479 U. S. 255.
Consolidated Edison Co., 447 U.S. at
447 U. S. 541,
n. 10;
see also Virginia Board of Pharmacy v. Virginia Citizens
Consumer Council, Inc., 425 U. S. 748,
425 U. S. 757,
n. 15 (1976). As the Court reaffirmed just two Terms ago,
"[t]he First Amendment protects appellees' right not only to
advocate their cause but also to select what they believe to be the
most effective means for so doing."
Meyer v. Grant, 486 U.S. at
486 U. S.
424.
The secondhand endorsement structure required by the Michigan
state law debases the value of the voice of nonprofit corporate
speakers. The public is not interested in what a PAC says; it does
care what the group itself says, so that the group itself can be
given credit or blame for the candidates it has endorsed or
opposed. PAC's suffer from a poor public image.
See App.
92a, 104a, 108a. An advertisement for which a nonprofit group takes
direct responsibility, in all likelihood, will have more
credibility and generate less distrust than one funded by a PAC.
PAC's are interim,
ad hoc organizations
Page 494 U. S. 709
with little continuity or responsibility. The respected
organizations affected by this case have a continuity, a stability
and an influence that makes it critical for their members and the
public at large to evaluate their official policies to determine
whether the organization has earned credibility over a period of
time. If a particular organization supports a candidate who injures
its cause or offends its ideals, the organization itself, not some
intermediary committee, ought to take the blame. It is a sad irony
that the group before us wishes to assume that responsibility, but
the action of the State, endorsed by this Court, does not allow it
to do so.
The diffusion of the corporate message produced by the PAC
requirement also ensures a lack of fit between the statute's ends
and its means. If the concern is that nonprofit corporate speech
distorts the political process, it would seem that injecting the
confusion of a PAC as an intermediary, albeit one controlled and
directed by the corporation, further diffuses responsibility. Even
if there were any possibility of corruption by allowing the
Michigan Chamber of Commerce to finance the proposed advertisement
supporting a candidate, it makes no sense to argue that such a
possibility would be eliminated by requiring the disclaimer at the
bottom to read "Paid for by the Michigan Chamber of Commerce PAC"
rather than "Paid for by the Michigan Chamber of Commerce."
The majority relies on the state interest in protecting members
from the use of nonprofit corporate funds to support candidates
whom they may oppose. We should reject this interest as
insufficient to save the Act here, just as we rejected the argument
in
Bellotti, 435 U.S. at
435 U. S.
792-793.
See also Consolidated Edison Co.,
supra, at
447 U. S.
543.
The Court takes refuge in the argument that some members or
contributors to nonprofit corporations may find their own views
distorted by the organization, and cites our holding in
Abood
v. Detroit Board of Education, 431 U.
S. 209 (1977).
Abood does not apply here, as
the disincentives to dissociate are not comparable.
Bellotti,
supra, at
435 U. S. 794,
n. 34 (noting "crucial distinction" between union members and
Page 494 U. S. 710
shareholders). One need not become a member of the Michigan
Chamber of Commerce or the Sierra Club in order to earn a living.
To the extent that members disagree with a nonprofit corporation's
policies, they can seek change from within, withhold financial
support, cease to associate with the group, or form a rival group
of their own. Allowing government to use the excuse of protecting
shareholder rights to stifle the speech of private, voluntary
organizations undermines the First Amendment.
To create second-class speakers that can be stifled on the
subject of candidate qualifications is to silence some of the most
significant participants in the American public dialogue, as
evidenced by the
amici briefs filed on behalf of the
Chamber of Commerce by the American Civil Liberties Union, the
Center for Public Interest Law, the American Medical Association,
the National Association of Realtors, the American Insurance
Association, the National Organization for Women, Greenpeace
Action, the National Abortion Rights Action League, the National
Right to Work Committee, the Planned Parenthood Federation of
America, the Fund for the Feminist Majority, the Washington Legal
Foundation, and the Allied Educational Foundation. I reject any
argument based on the idea that these groups and their views are
not of importance and value to the self-fulfillment and
self-expression of their members, and to the rich public dialogue
that must be the mark of any free society. To suggest otherwise is
contrary to the American political experience and our own judicial
knowledge.
It is a distinctive part of the American character for
individuals to join associations to enrich the public dialogue.
See, e.g., R. Horn, Groups and the Constitution 13-18
(1956). The theme of group identity is part of the history of
American democracy.
See, e.g., The Federalist No. 10 (J.
Madison). As de Toqueville observed:
"Americans of all ages, all conditions, and all dispositions
constantly form associations. They have not only commercial
Page 494 U. S. 711
and manufacturing companies, in which all take part, but
associations of a thousand other kinds, religious, moral, serious,
futile, general or restricted, enormous or diminutive. . . . If it
is proposed to inculcate some truth or to foster some feeling by
the encouragement of a great example, they form a society. Wherever
at the head of some new undertaking you see the government in
France, or a man of rank in England, in the United States you will
be sure to find an association."
2 A. de Toqueville, Democracy in America 106 (P. Bradley ed.
1948).
Finally, the majority's conclusion that the statute is not
overinclusive because independent expenditures by nonprofit
corporations may be assumed to have a pernicious, distorting effect
on political processes does not withstand the rigorous scrutiny
applicable to bans on speech.
See NCPAC, 470 U.S. at
470 U. S. 501.
It even contradicts
MCFL, where we said: "[A]ssociations
do not suddenly present the specter of corruption merely by
assuming the corporate form." 479 U.S. at
479 U. S. 263.
The Court reasons that the Chamber of Commerce benefits from a
"unique state-conferred corporate structure that facilitates the
amassing of large treasuries."
Ante at
494 U. S. 660.
This proposition is not self-evident, and has little or no relation
to the suppression of ideas. The reality, of course, is that some
groups and organizations, particularly those with many members, may
find that the nonprofit corporate form is the only feasible way of
organizing so that they can transmit important views to the public
as a whole. Because the unincorporated association structure
carries with it a high risk of personal liability for members and
operates in an uncertain legal climate, groups often prefer to
organize in nonprofit corporate form. The corporate form provides
clear rights and responsibilities and limits the liability of
members. E. Hadden & B. French, Nonprofit Organizations 12
(1987); H. Oleck, Nonprofit Corporations, Organizations and
Associations 30-31 (4th ed. 1982); M. Lane, Legal
Page 494 U. S. 712
Handbook for Nonprofit Organizations 4, 22-26, 43, 59-61, 124
(1980). For these reasons, in recent years the number of important
unincorporated associations has dwindled, while the number of
incorporated associations has proliferated. Oleck,
supra
at 31. By deciding to operate as a nonprofit corporation rather
than an unincorporated association, a group does not forfeit its
First Amendment protection to participate in political
discourse.
III
An independent ground for invalidating this statute is the
blanket exemption for media corporations. It is beyond peradventure
that the media could not be prohibited from speaking about
candidate qualifications. The First Amendment would not tolerate a
law prohibiting a newspaper or television network from spending on
political comment because it operates through a corporation.
See Mills v. Alabama, 384 U. S. 214,
384 U. S.
218-220 (1966). As Justice BRENNAN, joined by a majority
of the Court in
Dun & Bradstreet, Inc. v. Greenmoss
Builders, Inc., 472 U. S. 749
(1985), stated "the rights of the institutional media are no
greater and no less than those enjoyed by other individuals or
organizations engaged in the same activities."
Id. at
472 U. S. 784
(BRENNAN, J., dissenting, joined by MARSHALL, BLACKMUN, and
STEVENS, JJ.);
id. at
472 U. S. 773
(WHITE, J., concurring in judgment) ("the First Amendment gives no
more protection to the press . . . than it does to others
exercising their freedom of speech"). The argument relied on by the
majority, that media corporations are in the business of
communicating and other corporations are not, is unsatisfying. All
corporations communicate with the public to some degree, whether it
is their business or not, and communication is of particular
importance for nonprofit corporations.
The web of corporate ownership that links media and nonmedia
corporations is difficult to untangle for the purpose
Page 494 U. S. 713
of any meaningful distinction. Newspapers, television networks,
and other media may be owned by parent corporations with multiple
business interests. Nothing in the statutory scheme prohibits a
business corporate parent from directing its newspaper to support
or oppose a particular candidate. The Act not only permits that
discretion or control, but makes it a crime for a public interest
nonprofit corporation to bring to light such activity if to do so
infers candidate support or opposition. I can find no permissible
basis under the First Amendment for the States to make this
unsupported distinction among corporate speakers.
IV
The Court's hostility to the corporate form used by the speaker
in this case and its assertion that corporate wealth is the evil to
be regulated is far too imprecise to justify the most severe
restriction on political speech ever sanctioned by this Court. In
any event, this distinction is irrelevant to a nonprofit
corporation.
"Where at all possible, government must curtail speech only to
the degree necessary to meet the particular problem at hand, and
must avoid infringing on speech that does not pose the danger that
has prompted regulation."
MCFL, 479 U.S. at
479 U. S. 265.
The wholesale ban on corporate political speech enacted by the
Michigan legislature is "too blunt an instrument for such a
delicate task."
Ibid.
By constructing a rationale for the jurisprudence of this Court
that prevents distinguished organizations in public affairs from
announcing that a candidate is qualified or not qualified for
public office, the Court imposes its own model of speech, one far
removed from economic and political reality. It is an unhappy
paradox that this Court, which has the role of protecting speech
and of barring censorship from all aspects of political life, now
becomes itself the censor. In the course of doing so, the Court
reveals a lack of concern for speech rights that have the full
protection of the First Amendment. I would affirm the judgment.
[
Footnote 3/1]
Section 54 of the Michigan Campaign Finance Act states:
"Sec. 54. (1) Except with respect to the exceptions and
conditions in subsections (2) and (3) and section 55, and to loans
made in the ordinary course of business, a corporation may not make
a contribution or expenditure or provide volunteer personal
services which services are excluded from the definition of a
contribution pursuant to section 4(3)(a)."
"
* * * *"
"(4) Nothing in this section shall preclude a corporation or
joint stock company from making an independent expenditure in any
amount for the qualification, passage, or defeat of a ballot
question. A corporation making an independent expenditure under
this subsection shall be considered a ballot question committee for
the purposes of this act."
Mich.Comp. Laws § 169.254 (1979).
[
Footnote 3/2]
Section 6 of the Michigan Campaign Finance Act provides:
"Sec. 6. (1) 'Expenditure' means a payment, donation, loan,
pledge, or promise of payment of money or anything of ascertainable
monetary value for goods, materials, services, or facilities in
assistance of, or in opposition to, the nomination or election of a
candidate, or the qualification, passage, or defeat of a ballot
question. . . . "
"(2) Expenditure includes a contribution or a transfer of
anything of ascertainable monetary value for purposes of
influencing the nomination or election of any candidate or the
qualification, passage, or defeat of a ballot question."
"(3) Expenditure does not include:"
"
* * * *"
"(c) An expenditure for communication on a subject or issue if
the communication does not support or oppose a ballot issue or
candidate by name or clear inference or an expenditure for the
establishment, administration, or solicitation of contributions to
a fund or independent committee."
"(d) An expenditure by a broadcasting station, newspaper,
magazine, or other periodical or publication for any news story,
commentary, or editorial in support of or opposition to a candidate
for elective office, or a ballot question in the regular course of
publication or broadcasting."
Mich.Comp. Laws § 169.206 (1979).
[
Footnote 3/3]
Section 9(1) states:
"Sec. 9. (1) 'Independent expenditure' means an expenditure as
defined in section 6 by a person if the expenditure is not made at
the direction of or under the control of, another person and if the
expenditure is not a contribution to a committee."
Mich.Comp. Laws § 169.209(1) (1979).
[
Footnote 3/4]
See 494
U.S. 652fn3/2|>n. 2,
supra.
[
Footnote 3/5]
Section 54(5) states:
"(5) A person who knowingly violates this section is guilty of a
felony and shall be punished by a fine of not more than $5,000.00
or imprisonment for not more than 3 years, or both, and if the
person is other than an individual, the person shall be fined not
more than $10,000.00."
Mich.Comp. Laws § 169.254(5) (1979).
[
Footnote 3/6]
As the primary objective of the statute is itself prohibited by
the First Amendment, there is no need to explain that the statute
is invalid also because it is vague and imprecise. It should be
noted, however, that the criminal prohibition of speech which by
"inference" can be taken to support a candidate,
see
Mich.Comp. Laws § 169.206(3)(c) (1979), must in itself chill
speech on public issues, which the Court has already found
protected in
Bellotti.