Petitioner in No. 87-5765 was approximately 17 years and 4
months old at the time he committed murder in Kentucky. A juvenile
court, after conducting hearings, transferred him for trial as an
adult under a state statute permitting such action as to offenders
who are either charged with a Class A felony or capital crime or
who are over the age of 16 and charged with a felony. Petitioner
was convicted and sentenced to death. The State Supreme Court
affirmed the death sentence, rejecting petitioner's contention that
he had a constitutional right to treatment in the juvenile justice
system, and declaring that his age and the possibility that he
might be rehabilitated were mitigating factors properly left to the
jury. Petitioner in No. 87-6026, who was approximately 16 years and
6 months old when he committed murder in Missouri, was certified
for trial as an adult under a state statute permitting such action
against individuals between 14 and 17 years old who have committed
felonies. He pleaded guilty and was sentenced to death. The State
Supreme Court affirmed, rejecting his contention that the sentence
violated the Eighth Amendment.
Held: The judgments are affirmed.
No. 87-5765,
734
S.W.2d 781, affirmed; No. 87-6026,
736 S.W.2d
409, affirmed.
JUSTICE SCALIA delivered the opinion of the Court with respect
to Parts I, II, III, and IV-A, concluding that the imposition of
capital punishment on an individual for a crime committed at 16 or
17 years of age does not constitute cruel and unusual punishment
under the Eighth Amendment. Pp.
492 U. S.
365-374.
(a) Whether a particular punishment violates the Eighth
Amendment depends on whether it constitutes one of "those modes or
acts of punishment . . . considered cruel and unusual at the time
that the Bill of Rights was adopted,"
Ford v. Wainwright,
477 U. S. 399,
477 U. S. 405,
or is contrary to the "evolving standards of decency that mark the
progress of a maturing society,"
Trop v. Dulles,
356 U. S. 86,
356 U. S. 101.
Petitioners have not alleged that their sentences would have been
considered cruel and unusual in the 18th century, and could not
support such a contention, since, at that
Page 492 U. S. 362
time, the common law set the rebuttable presumption of
incapacity to commit felonies (which were punishable by death) at
the age of 14. In accordance with this common law tradition, at
least 281 offenders under 18, and 126 under 17, have been executed
in this country. Pp.
492 U. S.
368-370.
(b) In determining whether a punishment violates evolving
standards of decency, this Court looks not to its own subjective
conceptions, but, rather, to the conceptions of modern American
society as reflected by objective evidence.
E.g., Coker v.
Georgia, 433 U. S. 584,
433 U. S. 592.
The primary and most reliable evidence of national consensus -- the
pattern of federal and state laws -- fails to meet petitioner's
heavy burden of proving a settled consensus against the execution
of 16- and 17-year-old offenders. Of the 37 States that permit
capital punishment, 15 decline to impose it on 16-year-olds and 12
on 17-year-olds. This does not establish the degree of national
agreement this Court has previously thought sufficient to label a
punishment cruel and unusual.
See Tison v. Arizona,
481 U. S. 137,
481 U. S. 154.
Pp.
492 U. S.
370-373.
(c) Nor is there support for petitioners' argument that a
demonstrable reluctance of juries to impose, and prosecutors to
seek, capital sentences for 16- and 17-year-olds establishes a
societal consensus that such sentences are inappropriate.
Statistics showing that a far smaller number of offenders under 18
than over 18 have been sentenced to death reflect in part the fact
that a far smaller percentage of capital crimes is committed by
persons in the younger age group. Beyond that, it is likely that
the very considerations that induce petitioners to believe death
should
never be imposed on such young offenders cause
prosecutors and juries to believe it should
rarely be
imposed, so that the statistics are no proof of a categorical
aversion. Pp.
492 U. S.
373-374.
JUSTICE SCALIA, joined by THE CHIEF JUSTICE, JUSTICE WHITE, and
JUSTICE KENNEDY, concluded in Parts IV-B and V that:
1. There is no relevance to the state laws cited by petitioners
which set 18 or more as the legal age for engaging in various
activities, ranging from driving to drinking alcoholic beverages to
voting. Those laws operate in gross, and do not conduct
individualized maturity tests for each driver, drinker, or voter;
an age appropriate in the vast majority of cases must therefore be
selected. In the realm of capital punishment, however,
individualized consideration is a constitutional requirement.
Twenty-nine States, including Kentucky and Missouri, have codified
this requirement in laws specifically designating age as a
mitigating factor that capital sentencers must be permitted to
consider. Moreover, the determinations required by transfer
statutes such as Kentucky's and Missouri's to certify a juvenile
for trial as an adult ensure individualized consideration of the
maturity and moral responsibility of 16- and 17-year-olds before
they are even held to stand trial as adults. It is those
particularized laws, rather than the generalized driving, drinking,
and voting
Page 492 U. S. 363
laws, that display society's views on the age at which no
youthful offender should be held responsible. Pp.
492 U. S.
374-377.
2. The indicia of national consensus offered by petitioner other
than state and federal statutes and the behavior of prosecutors and
juries cannot establish constitutional standards. Public opinion
polls, the views of interest groups, and the positions of
professional associations are too uncertain a foundation for
constitutional law. Also insufficient is socioscientific or
ethicoscientific evidence tending to show that capital punishment
fails to deter 16- and 17-year-olds because they have a less highly
developed fear of death, and fails to exact just retribution
because juveniles, being less mature and responsible, are less
morally blameworthy. The audience for such arguments is not this
Court, but the citizenry. Although several of the Court's cases
have engaged in so-called "proportionality" analysis -- which
examines whether there is a disproportion between the punishment
imposed and the defendant's blameworthiness, and whether a
punishment makes any measurable contribution to acceptable goals of
punishment -- those decisions have never invalidated a punishment
on that basis alone, but have done so only when there was also
objective evidence of state laws or jury determinations
establishing a societal consensus against the penalty. Pp.
492 U. S.
377-380.
JUSTICE O'CONNOR, although agreeing that no national consensus
presently forbids the imposition of capital punishment on 16- or
17-year-old murderers, concluded that this Court has a
constitutional obligation to conduct proportionality analysis,
see, e.g., Penry v. Lynaugh, ante at
492 U. S.
335-340, and should consider age-based statutory
classifications that are relevant to that analysis. Pp.
492 U. S.
380-382.
SCALIA, J., announced the judgment of the Court and delivered
the opinion of the Court with respect to Parts I, II, III, and
IV-A, in which REHNQUIST, C. J., and WHITE, O'CONNOR, and KENNEDY,
JJ., joined, and an opinion with respect to Parts IV-B and V, in
which REHNQUIST, C. J., and WHITE and KENNEDY, JJ., joined.
O'CONNOR, J., filed an opinion concurring in part and concurring in
the judgment,
post, p.
492 U. S. 380.
BRENNAN, J., filed a dissenting opinion, in which MARSHALL,
BLACKMUN, and STEVENS, JJ., joined,
post, p.
492 U. S.
382.
Page 492 U. S. 364
JUSTICE SCALIA announced the judgment of the Court and delivered
the opinion of the Court with respect to Parts I, II, III, and
IV-A, and an opinion with respect to Parts IV-B and V, in which THE
CHIEF JUSTICE, JUSTICE WHITE, and JUSTICE KENNEDY join.
These two consolidated cases require us to decide whether the
imposition of capital punishment on an individual for a
Page 492 U. S. 365
crime committed at 16 or 17 years of age constitutes cruel and
unusual punishment under the Eighth Amendment.
I
The first case, No. 87-5765, involves the shooting death of
20-year-old Barbel Poore in Jefferson County, Kentucky. Petitioner
Kevin Stanford committed the murder on January 7, 1981, when he was
approximately 17 years and 4 months of age. Stanford and his
accomplice repeatedly raped and sodomized Poore during and after
their commission of a robbery at a gas station where she worked as
an attendant. They then drove her to a secluded area near the
station, where Stanford shot her pointblank in the face and then in
the back of her head. The proceeds from the robbery were roughly
300 cartons of cigarettes, two gallons of fuel, and a small amount
of cash. A corrections officer testified that petitioner explained
the murder as follows:
"'[H]e said, I had to shoot her, [she] lived next door to me and
she would recognize me. . . . I guess we could have tied her up or
something or beat [her up] . . . and tell her if she tells, we
would kill her. . . . Then after he said that, he started
laughing.'"
734
S.W.2d 781, 788 (Ky. 1987).
After Stanford's arrest, a Kentucky juvenile court conducted
hearings to determine whether he should be transferred for trial as
an adult under Ky.Rev.Stat.Ann. §208.170 (Michie 1982). That
statute provided that juvenile court jurisdiction could be waived
and an offender tried as an adult if he was either charged with a
Class A felony or capital crime, or was over 16 years of age and
charged with a felony. Stressing the seriousness of petitioner's
offenses and the unsuccessful attempts of the juvenile system to
treat him for numerous instances of past delinquency, the juvenile
court found certification for trial as an adult to be in the best
interest of petitioner and the community.
Page 492 U. S. 366
Stanford was convicted of murder, first-degree sodomy,
first-degree robbery, and receiving stolen property, and was
sentenced to death and 45 years in prison. The Kentucky Supreme
Court affirmed the death sentence, rejecting Stanford's "deman[d]
that he has a constitutional right to treatment." 734 S.W.2d at
792. Finding that the record clearly demonstrated that "there was
no program or treatment appropriate for the appellant in the
juvenile justice system," the court held that the juvenile court
did not err in certifying petitioner for trial as an adult. The
court also stated that petitioner's
"age and the possibility that he might be rehabilitated were
mitigating factors appropriately left to the consideration of the
jury that tried him."
Ibid.
The second case before us today, No. 87-6026, involves the
stabbing death of Nancy Allen, a 26-year-old mother of two who was
working behind the sales counter of the convenience store she and
David Allen owned and operated in Avondale, Missouri. Petitioner
Heath Wilkins committed the murder on July 27, 1985, when he was
approximately 16 years and 6 months of age. The record reflects
that Wilkins' plan was to rob the store and murder "whoever was
behind the counter" because "a dead person can't talk." While
Wilkins' accomplice, Patrick Stevens, held Allen, Wilkins stabbed
her, causing her to fall to the floor. When Stevens had trouble
operating the cash register, Allen spoke up to assist him, leading
Wilkins to stab her three more times in her chest. Two of these
wounds penetrated the victim's heart. When Allen began to beg for
her life, Wilkins stabbed her four more times in the neck, opening
her carotid artery. After helping themselves to liquor, cigarettes,
rolling papers, and approximately $450 in cash and checks, Wilkins
and Stevens left Allen to die on the floor.
Because he was roughly six months short of the age of majority
for purposes of criminal prosecution, Mo.Rev.Stat. §211.021(1)
(1986), Wilkins could not automatically be
Page 492 U. S. 367
tried as an adult under Missouri law. Before that could happen,
the juvenile court was required to terminate juvenile court
jurisdiction and certify Wilkins for trial as an adult under
§211.071, which permits individuals between 14 and 17 years of
age who have committed felonies to be tried as adults. Relying on
the "viciousness, force and violence" of the alleged crime,
petitioner's maturity, and the failure of the juvenile justice
system to rehabilitate him after previous delinquent acts, the
juvenile court made the necessary certification.
Wilkins was charged with first-degree murder, armed criminal
action, and carrying a concealed weapon. After the court found him
competent, petitioner entered guilty pleas to all charges. A
punishment hearing was held, at which both the State and petitioner
himself urged imposition of the death sentence. Evidence at the
hearing revealed that petitioner had been in and out of juvenile
facilities since the age of eight for various acts of burglary,
theft, and arson, had attempted to kill his mother by putting
insecticide into Tylenol capsules, and had killed several animals
in his neighborhood. Although psychiatric testimony indicated that
Wilkins had "personality disorders," the witnesses agreed that
Wilkins was aware of his actions and could distinguish right from
wrong.
Determining that the death penalty was appropriate, the trial
court entered the following order:
"[T]he court finds beyond reasonable doubt that the following
aggravating circumstances exist:"
"1. The murder in the first degree was committed while the
defendant was engaged in the perpetration of the felony of robbery,
and"
"2. The murder in the first degree involved depravity of mind
and that, as a result thereof, it was outrageously or wantonly
vile, horrible or inhuman."
App. in No. 876026, p. 77.
Page 492 U. S. 368
On mandatory review of Wilkins' death sentence, the Supreme
Court of Missouri affirmed, rejecting the argument that the
punishment violated the Eighth Amendment.
736 S.W.2d
409 (1987).
We granted certiorari in these cases, 488 U.S. 887 (1988) and
487 U.S. 1233 (1988), to decide whether the Eighth Amendment
precludes the death penalty for individuals who commit crimes at 16
or 17 years of age.
II
The thrust of both Wilkins' and Stanford's arguments is that
imposition of the death penalty on those who were juveniles when
they committed their crimes falls within the Eighth Amendment's
prohibition against "cruel and unusual punishments." Wilkins would
have us define juveniles as individuals 16 years of age and under;
Stanford would draw the line at 17.
Neither petitioner asserts that his sentence constitutes one of
"those modes or acts of punishment that had been considered cruel
and unusual at the time that the Bill of Rights was adopted."
Ford v. Wainwright, 477 U. S. 399,
477 U. S. 405
(1986). Nor could they support such a contention. At that time, the
common law set the rebuttable presumption of incapacity to commit
any felony at the age of 14, and theoretically permitted capital
punishment to be imposed on anyone over the age of 7.
See
4 W. Blackstone, Commentaries *23-24; 1 M. Hale, Pleas of the Crown
24-29 (1800).
See also In re Gault, 387 U. S.
1,
387 U. S. 16
(1967); Streib, Death Penalty for Children: The American Experience
with Capital Punishment for Crimes Committed While Under Age
Eighteen, 36 Okla.L.Rev. 613, 614-615 (1983); Kean, The History of
the Criminal Liability of Children, 53 L.Q.Rev. 364, 369-370
(1937). In accordance with the standards of this common law
tradition, at least 281 offenders under the age of 18 have been
executed in this country, and at least 126 under the age of 17.
See V. Streib, Death Penalty for Juveniles 57 (1987).
Page 492 U. S. 369
Thus, petitioners are left to argue that their punishment is
contrary to the "evolving standards of decency that mark the
progress of a maturing society,"
Trop v. Dulles,
356 U. S. 86,
356 U. S. 101
(1958) (plurality opinion). They are correct in asserting that this
Court has "not confined the prohibition embodied in the Eighth
Amendment to
barbarous' methods that were generally outlawed in
the 18th century," but instead has interpreted the Amendment "in a
flexible and dynamic manner." Gregg v. Georgia,
428 U. S. 153,
428 U. S. 171
(1976) (opinion of Stewart, Powell, and STEVENS, JJ.). In
determining what standards have "evolved," however, we have looked
not to our own conceptions of decency, but to those of modern
American society as a whole. [Footnote 1] As we have said,
"Eighth Amendment judgments should not be, or appear to be,
merely the subjective views of individual Justices; judgment should
be informed by objective factors to the maximum possible
extent."
Coker v. Georgia, 433 U. S. 584,
433 U. S. 592
(1977) (plurality opinion).
See also Penry v. Lynaugh,
ante at
492 U. S. 331;
Ford v. Wainwright, supra at
477 U. S. 406;
Enmund v. Florida, 458 U. S. 782,
458 U. S.
788-789 (1982);
Furman v. Georgia, 408 U.
S. 238,
408 U. S. 277
--
428 U. S. 279
(1972) (BRENNAN, J., concurring). This approach is dictated both by
the language of the Amendment -- which proscribes only those
punishments that are both "cruel and
unusual" -- and by
the "deference we owe to the decisions
Page 492 U. S. 370
of the state legislatures under our federal system,"
Gregg
v. Georgia, supra, at
428 U. S. 176.
III
"[F]irst" among the "
objective indicia that reflect the
public attitude toward a given sanction'" are statutes passed by
society's elected representatives. McCleskey v. Kemp,
481 U. S. 279,
481 U. S. 300
(1987), quoting Gregg v. Georgia, supra, at 428 U. S. 173.
Of the 37 States whose laws permit capital punishment, 15 decline
to impose it upon 16-year-old offenders and 12 decline to impose it
on 17-year-old offenders. [Footnote
2] This does
Page 492 U. S. 371
not establish the degree of national consensus this Court has
previously thought sufficient to label a particular punishment
cruel and unusual. In invalidating the death penalty for rape of an
adult woman, we stressed that Georgia was the
sole
jurisdiction that authorized such a punishment.
See Coker v.
Georgia, supra, at
433 U. S.
595-596. In striking down capital punishment for
participation in a robbery in which an accomplice takes a life, we
emphasized that only eight jurisdictions authorized similar
punishment.
Enmund v. Florida, supra, at
458 U. S. 792.
In finding that the Eighth Amendment precludes execution of the
insane, and thus requires an adequate hearing on the issue of
sanity, we relied upon (in addition to the common law rule) the
fact that "no State in the Union" permitted such punishment.
Ford v. Wainwright, 477 U.S. at
477 U. S. 408.
And in striking down a life sentence without parole under a
recidivist statute, we stressed that "[i]t appears that
[petitioner] was treated more severely than he would have been in
any other State."
Solem v. Helm, 463 U.
S. 277,
463 U. S. 300
(1983).
Since a majority of the States that permit capital punishment
authorize it for crimes committed at age 16 or above, [
Footnote 3] petitioners' cases are more
analogous to
Tison v. Arizona, 481 U.
S. 137 (1987), than
Coker, Enmund, Ford, and
Solem. In
Tison, which upheld Arizona's
imposition of the death penalty for major participation in a felony
with reckless indifference to human life, we noted that only 11 of
those jurisdictions
Page 492 U. S. 372
imposing capital punishment rejected its use in such
circumstances.
Id. at
481 U. S. 154.
As we noted earlier, here the number is 15 for offenders under 17,
and 12 for offenders under 18. We think the same conclusion as in
Tison is required in this case.
Petitioners make much of the recently enacted federal statute
providing capital punishment for certain drug-related offenses, but
limiting that punishment to offenders 18 and over. The Anti-Drug
Abuse Act of 1988, Pub.L. 100-690, 102 Stat. 4390, §7001(1),
21 U.S.C. §848(1) (1988 ed.). That reliance is entirely
misplaced. To begin with, the statute in question does not embody a
judgment by the Federal Legislature that no murder is heinous
enough to warrant the execution of such a youthful offender, but
merely that the narrow class of offense it defines is not. The
congressional judgment on the broader question, if apparent at all,
is to be found in the law that permits 16- and 17-year-olds (after
appropriate findings) to be tried and punished as adults for all
federal offenses, including those bearing a capital penalty that is
not limited to 18-year-olds. [
Footnote 4]
See 18 U.S.C. §5032 (1982 ed.,
Supp. V). Moreover, even if it were true that no
Page 492 U. S. 373
federal statute permitted the execution of persons under 18,
that would not remotely establish -- in the face of a substantial
number of state statutes to the contrary -- a national consensus
that such punishment is inhumane, any more than the absence of a
federal lottery establishes a national consensus that lotteries are
socially harmful. To be sure, the absence of a federal death
penalty for 16- or 17-year-olds (if it existed) might be evidence
that there is no national consensus in favor of such punishment. It
is not the burden of Kentucky and Missouri, however, to establish a
national consensus approving what their citizens have voted to do;
rather, it is the "heavy burden" of petitioners,
Gregg v.
Georgia, 428 U.S. at
428 U. S. 175,
to establish a national consensus against it. As far as the primary
and most reliable indication of consensus is concerned -- the
pattern of enacted laws -- petitioners have failed to carry that
burden.
IV
A
Wilkins and Stanford argue, however, that even if the laws
themselves do not establish a settled consensus, the application of
the laws does. That contemporary society views capital punishment
of 16- and 17-year-old offenders as inappropriate is demonstrated,
they say, by the reluctance of juries to impose, and prosecutors to
seek, such sentences. Petitioners are quite correct that a far
smaller number of offenders under 18 than over 18 have been
sentenced to death in this country. From 1982 through 1988, for
example, out of 2,106 total death sentences, only 15 were imposed
on individuals who were 16 or under when they committed their
crimes, and only 30 on individuals who were 17 at the time of the
crime.
See Streib, Imposition of Death Sentences For
Juvenile Offenses, January 1, 1982, Through April 1, 1989, p. 2
(paper for Cleveland-Marshall College of Law, April 5, 1989). And
it appears that actual executions for crimes committed under age 18
accounted for only about two percent of the total number of
executions that occurred between 1642
Page 492 U. S. 374
and 1986.
See Streib, Death Penalty for Juveniles, at
55, 57. As Wilkins points out, the last execution of a person who
committed a crime under 17 years of age occurred in 1959. These
statistics, however, carry little significance. Given the
undisputed fact that a far smaller percentage of capital crimes are
committed by persons under 18 than over 18, the discrepancy in
treatment is much less than might seem. Granted, however, that a
substantial discrepancy exists, that does not establish the
requisite proposition that the death sentence for offenders under
18 is categorically unacceptable to prosecutors and juries. To the
contrary, it is not only possible, but overwhelmingly probable,
that the very considerations which induce petitioners and their
supporters to believe that death should
never be imposed
on offenders under 18 cause prosecutors and juries to believe that
it should
rarely be imposed.
This last point suggests why there is also no relevance to the
laws cited by petitioners and their
amici which set 18 or
more as the legal age for engaging in various activities, ranging
from driving to drinking alcoholic beverages to voting. It is, to
begin with, absurd to think that one must be mature enough to drive
carefully, to drink responsibly, or to vote intelligently, in order
to be mature enough to understand that murdering another human
being is profoundly wrong, and to conform one's conduct to that
most minimal of all civilized standards. But even if the requisite
degrees of maturity were comparable, the age statutes in question
would still not be relevant. They do not represent a social
judgment that all persons under the designated ages are not
responsible enough to drive, to drink, or to vote, but at most a
judgment that the vast majority are not. These laws set the
appropriate ages for the operation of a system that makes its
determinations in gross, and that does not conduct individualized
maturity tests for each driver, drinker, or voter. The
Page 492 U. S. 375
criminal justice system, however, does provide individualized
testing. In the realm of capital punishment in particular,
"individualized consideration [is] a constitutional requirement,"
Lockett v. Ohio, 438 U. S. 586,
438 U. S. 605
(1978) (opinion of Burger, C. J.) (footnote omitted);
see also
Zant v. Stephens, 462 U. S. 862,
462 U. S. 879
(1983) (collecting cases), and one of the individualized mitigating
factors that sentencers must be permitted to consider is the
defendant's age,
see Eddings v. Oklahoma, 455 U.
S. 104,
455 U. S.
115-116 (1982). Twenty-nine States, including both
Kentucky and Missouri, have codified this constitutional
requirement in laws specifically designating the defendant's age as
a mitigating factor in capital cases. [
Footnote 5] Moreover, the determinations required by
juvenile transfer statutes to certify a juvenile for trial as an
adult ensure individualized consideration of the maturity and moral
responsibility of 16- and 17-year-old offenders before they are
even held to stand trial as adults. [
Footnote 6] The application of this
Page 492 U. S. 376
particularized system to the petitioners can be declared
constitutionally inadequate only if there is a consensus, not that
17 or 18 is the age at which most persons, or even almost all
persons, achieve sufficient maturity to be held fully responsible
for murder; but that 17 or 18 is the age before which
no
one can reasonably be held fully responsible. What displays
society's views on this latter point are not the ages set forth in
the generalized system of driving, drinking, and voting laws cited
by petitioners and their
amici, but the ages at
Page 492 U. S. 377
which the States permit their particularized capital punishment
systems to be applied. [
Footnote
7]
V
Having failed to establish a consensus against capital
punishment for 16- and 17-year-old offenders through state and
federal statutes and the behavior of prosecutors and juries,
petitioners seek to demonstrate it through other indicia, including
public opinion polls, the views of interest groups, and the
positions adopted by various professional associations. We decline
the invitation to rest constitutional law upon such uncertain
foundations. A revised national consensus so broad, so clear, and
so enduring as to justify a permanent prohibition upon all units of
democratic government must appear in the operative acts (laws and
the application of laws) that the people have approved.
We also reject petitioners' argument that we should invalidate
capital punishment of 16- and 17-year-old offenders on the ground
that it fails to serve the legitimate goals of penology. According
to petitioners, it fails to deter because juveniles, possessing
less developed cognitive skills than adults, are less likely to
fear death; and it fails to exact just retribution because
juveniles, being less mature and responsible, are also less morally
blameworthy. In support of these claims, petitioners and their
supporting
amici marshall an array of
Page 492 U. S. 378
socioscientific evidence concerning the psychological and
emotional development of 16- and 17-year-olds.
If such evidence could conclusively establish the entire lack of
deterrent effect and moral responsibility, resort to the Cruel and
Unusual Punishments Clause would be unnecessary; the Equal
Protection Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment would invalidate
these laws for lack of rational basis.
See Dallas v.
Stanglin, 490 U. S. 19
(1989). But as the adjective "socioscientific" suggests (and
insofar as evaluation of moral responsibility is concerned perhaps
the adjective "ethicoscientific" would be more apt), it is not
demonstrable that no 16-year-old is "adequately responsible" or
significantly deterred. It is rational, even if mistaken, to think
the contrary. The battle must be fought, then, on the field of the
Eighth Amendment; and, in that struggle, socioscientific,
ethicoscientific, or even purely scientific evidence is not an
available weapon. The punishment is either "cruel
and
unusual" (
i.e., society has set its face against it) or it
is not. The audience for these arguments, in other words, is not
this Court, but the citizenry of the United States. It is they, not
we, who must be persuaded. For, as we stated earlier, our job is to
identify the "evolving standards of decency"; to
determine, not what they
should be, but what they
are. We have no power under the Eighth Amendment to
substitute our belief in the scientific evidence for the society's
apparent skepticism. In short, we emphatically reject petitioner's
suggestion that the issues in this case permit us to apply our "own
informed judgment," Brief for Petitioner in No. 876026, p. 23,
regarding the desirability of permitting the death penalty for
crimes by 16- and 17-year-olds.
We reject the dissent's contention that our approach, by
"largely return[ing] the task of defining the contours of Eighth
Amendment protection to political majorities," leaves
"
[c]onstitutional doctrine [to] be formulated by the acts of
those institutions which the Constitution is supposed to limit,'"
post at 492 U. S. 391,
492 U. S. 392
(citation omitted). When this Court
Page 492 U. S. 379
cast loose from the historical moorings consisting of the
original application of the Eighth Amendment, it did not embark
rudderless upon a wide-open sea. Rather, it limited the Amendment's
extension to those practices contrary to the "evolving
standards of decency that mark the progress of a maturing
society."
Trop v. Dulles, 356 U.S. at
356 U. S. 101
(plurality opinion) (emphasis added). It has never been thought
that this was a shorthand reference to the preferences of a
majority of this Court. By reaching a decision supported neither by
constitutional text nor by the demonstrable current standards of
our citizens, the dissent displays a failure to appreciate that
"those institutions which the Constitution is supposed to limit"
include the Court itself. To say, as the dissent says, that "`it is
for
us ultimately to judge whether the Eighth Amendment
permits imposition of the death penalty,'"
post at
492 U. S. 391
(emphasis added), quoting
Enmund v. Florida, 458 U.S. at
458 U. S. 797
-- and to mean that as the dissent means it,
i.e., that it
is for
us to judge, not on the basis of what we perceive
the Eighth Amendment originally prohibited, or on the basis of what
we perceive the society through its democratic processes now
overwhelmingly disapproves, but on the basis of what we think
"proportionate" and "measurably contributory to acceptable goals of
punishment" -- to say and mean that, is to replace judges of the
law with a committee of philosopher-kings.
While the dissent is correct that several of our cases have
engaged in so-called "proportionality" analysis, examining whether
"there is a disproportion 'between the punishment imposed and the
defendant's blameworthiness,'" and whether a punishment makes any
"measurable contribution to acceptable goals of punishment,"
see post at
492 U. S. 393,
we have never invalidated a punishment on this basis alone. All of
our cases condemning a punishment under this mode of analysis also
found that the objective indicators of state laws or jury
determinations evidenced a societal consensus against that penalty.
See Solem v. Helm, 463 U.S. at
463 U. S.
299-300;
Page 492 U. S. 380
Enmund v. Florida, supra, at
458 U. S.
789-796;
Coker v. Georgia, 433 U.S. at
433 U. S.
593-597 (plurality opinion). In fact, the two
methodologies blend into one another, since "proportionality"
analysis itself can only be conducted on the basis of the standards
set by our own society; the only alternative, once again, would be
our personal preferences.
* * * *
We discern neither a historical nor a modern societal consensus
forbidding the imposition of capital punishment on any person who
murders at 16 or 17 years of age. Accordingly, we conclude that
such punishment does not offend the Eighth Amendment's prohibition
against cruel and unusual punishment.
The judgments of the Supreme Court of Kentucky and the Supreme
Court of Missouri are therefore
Affirmed.
* Together with No. 87-6026,
Wilkins v. Missouri, on
certiorari to the Supreme Court of Missouri.
[
Footnote 1]
We emphasize that it is
American conceptions of decency
that are dispositive, rejecting the contention of petitioners and
their various
amici (accepted by the dissent,
see
post at
492 U. S.
389-390) that the sentencing practices of other
countries are relevant. While
"[t]he practices of other nations, particularly other
democracies, can be relevant to determining whether a practice
uniform among our people is not merely an historical accident, but
rather so 'implicit in the concept of ordered liberty' that it
occupies a place not merely in our mores, but, text permitting, in
our Constitution as well,"
Thompson v. Oklahoma, 487 U. S. 815,
487 U. S.
868-869, n. 4 (1988) (SCALIA, J., dissenting), quoting
Palko v. Connecticut, 302 U. S. 319,
302 U. S. 325
(1937) (Cardozo, J.), they cannot serve to establish the first
Eighth Amendment prerequisite, that the practice is accepted among
our people.
[
Footnote 2]
The following States preclude capital punishment of offenders
under 18: California (Cal.Penal Code Ann. §190.5 (West 1988));
Colorado (Colo.Rev.Stat. §1611-103(1)(a) (1986)); Connecticut
(Conn.Gen.Stat. § 53a-46a(g)(1) (1989)); Illinois
(Ill.Rev.Stat., ch. 38, 119-1(b) (1987)); Maryland (Md.Ann.Code,
Art. 27, § 412(f) (Supp.1988)); Nebraska (Neb.Rev.Stat.
§28-105.01 (1985)); New Jersey (N.J.Stat.Ann.
§2A:4A-22(a) (West 1987) and 2C:11-3(g) (West Supp.1988)); New
Hampshire (N. H. Rev. Stat. Ann. §630: 5(XIII) (Supp. 1988));
New Mexico (N.M.Stat.Ann. §§ 28-6-1(A), 31-18-14(A)
(1987)); Ohio (Ohio Rev.Code Ann. §2929.02(A) (1987)); Oregon
(Ore.Rev.Stat. §§161.620 and 419.476(1) (1987));
Tennessee (Tenn.Code Ann. §§37-1-102(3), 37-1-102(4),
37-1103, 37-1-134(a)(1) (1984 and Supp. 1988)). Three more States
preclude the death penalty for offenders under 17: Georgia (Ga.Code
Ann. §17-9-3 (1982)); North Carolina (N.C.Gen.Stat.
§14-17 (Supp. 1988)); Texas (Tex.Penal Code Ann. §
8.07(d) (Supp. 1989)).
The dissent takes issue with our failure to include, among those
States evidencing a consensus against executing 16- and 17-year-old
offenders, the District of Columbia and the 14 States that do not
authorize capital punishment.
Post at
492 U. S.
384-385. It seems to us, however, that while the number
of those jurisdictions bears upon the question whether there is a
consensus against capital punishment altogether, it is quite
irrelevant to the specific inquiry in this case: whether there is a
settled consensus in favor of punishing offenders under 18
differently from those over 18 insofar as capital punishment is
concerned. The dissent's position is rather like discerning a
national consensus that wagering on cockfights is inhumane by
counting within that consensus those States that bar all wagering.
The issue in the present case is not whether capital punishment is
thought to be desirable, but whether persons under 18 are thought
to be specially exempt from it. With respect to that inquiry, it is
no more logical to say that the capital punishment laws of those
States which prohibit capital punishment (and thus do not address
age) support the dissent's position, than it would be to say that
the age-of-adult criminal responsibility laws of those same States
(which do not address capital punishment) support our position.
[
Footnote 3]
The dissent again works its statistical magic by refusing to
count among the States that authorize capital punishment of 16- and
17-year-old offenders those 19 States that set no minimum age in
their death penalty statute, and specifically permit 16- and
17-year-olds to be sentenced as adults.
Post at
492 U. S. 385.
We think that describing this position is adequate response.
[
Footnote 4]
See 10 U.S.C. § 906a (1982 ed., Supp. V)
(peacetime espionage); § 918 (murder by persons subject to
Uniform Code of Military Justice); 18 U.S.C. §§ 32, 33,
and 34 (1982 ed. and Supp. V) (destruction of aircraft, motor
vehicles, or related facilities resulting in death);
§116(b)(3) (1982 ed., Supp. V) (retaliatory murder of member
of immediate family of law enforcement officials) (by cross
reference to §1111 (1982 ed. and Supp. V)); § 351 (1982
ed. and Supp. V) (murder of Member of Congress, high-ranking
executive official, or Supreme Court Justice) (by cross reference
to §1111); §794 (1982 ed. and Supp. V) (espionage);
§844(f) (1982 ed., Supp. V) (destruction of Government
property resulting in death); §1111 (first-degree murder
within federal jurisdiction); §1716 (1982 ed. and Supp. V)
(mailing of injurious articles resulting in death); §1751
(assassination or kidnaping resulting in death of President or Vice
President); §1992 (willful wrecking of train resulting in
death); § 2113 (1982 ed. and Supp. V) (bank robbery-related
murder or kidnaping); § 2381 (treason); 49 U.S.C. App.
§§1472 and 1473 (1982 ed. and Supp. V) (death resulting
from aircraft hijacking).
[
Footnote 5]
See Ala. Code §13A-5-51 (7) (1982);
Ariz.Rev.Stat.Ann. §13703(G)(5) (Supp.1988); Ark.Code Ann.
§5-4-605(4) (1987); Cal.Penal Code Ann. §190.3(i) (West
1988); Colo.Rev.Stat. §16-11-103(5)(a) (1986); Conn.Gen.Stat.
§53a-46a(g)(1) (1989); Fla.Stat. §921.141(6)(g) (1987);
Ind.Code § 35-50-2-9(c)(7) (1988); Ky.Rev.Stat.Ann. §
532.025(2)(b)(8) (Baldwin 1988); La.Code Crim.Proc.Ann., Art.
905.5(f) (West 1984); Md.Ann.Code, Art. 27, §413(g)(5) (1988);
Miss.Code Ann. § 99-19-101(6)(g) (Supp.1988); Mo.Rev.Stat.
§ 565.032(3)(7) (1986); Mont.Code Ann. § 4618-304(7)
(1987); Neb.Rev.Stat. §29-2523(2)(d) (1985); Nev.Rev.Stat.
§200.035(6) (1987); N.H.Rev.Stat.Ann. §630: 5(II)(b)(5)
(1986); N.J.Stat.Ann. §2C:11-3(c)(5)(c) (West Supp.1988);
N.M.Stat.Ann. §3120A-6(I) (1987); N.C.Gen.Stat.
§15A-2000(f)(7) (1988); Ohio Rev.Code Ann. §2929.04(B)(4)
(1987); Ore.Rev.Stat. §163.150(1)(b)(B) (1987); 42
Pa.Cons.Stat. § 9711(e)(4) (1982); S.C.Code
§16-3-20(C)(b)(9) (Supp.1988); Tenn.Code Ann. §
39-2-203(j)(7) (1982); Utah Code Ann. § 76-3-207 (2)(e)
(Supp.1988); Va.Code §19.2-264.4(B)(v) (1983); Wash.Rev.Code
§10.95.070(7) (Supp.1989); Wyo.Stat. § 6-2-102(j)(vii)
(1988).
[
Footnote 6]
The Kentucky statute under which Stanford was certified to be
tried as an adult provides in relevant part:
"(3) If the court determines that probable cause exists [to
believe that a person 16 years old or older committed a felony or
that a person under 16 years of age committed a Class A felony or a
capital offense], it shall then determine if it is in the best
interest of the child and the community to order such a transfer
based upon the seriousness of the alleged offense; whether the
offense was against person or property, with greater weight being
given to offenses against persons; the maturity of the child as
determined by his environment; the child's prior record; and the
prospects for adequate protection of the public and the likelihood
of reasonable rehabilitation of the child by the use of procedures,
services, and facilities currently available to the juvenile
justice system."
Ky.Rev.Stat.Ann. § 208.170 (Michie 1982) (repealed
effective July 15, 1984).
The Missouri statute under which Wilkins was certified provides
that, in determining whether to transfer a juvenile the court must
consider:
"(1) The seriousness of the offense alleged and whether the
protection of the community requires transfer to the court of
general jurisdiction;"
"(2) Whether the offense alleged involved viciousness, force and
violence;"
"(3) Whether the offense alleged was against persons or property
with greater weight being given to the offense against persons,
especially if personal injury resulted;"
"(4) Whether the offense alleged is a part of a repetitive
pattern of offenses which indicates that the child may be beyond
rehabilitation under the juvenile code;"
"(5) The record and history of the child, including experience
with the juvenile justice system, other courts, supervision,
commitments to juvenile institutions and other placements;"
"(6) The sophistication and maturity of the child as determined
by consideration of his home and environmental situation, emotional
condition and pattern of living;"
"(7) The program and facilities available to the juvenile court
in considering disposition; and"
"(8) Whether or not the child can benefit from the treatment or
rehabilitative programs available to the juvenile court."
Mo.Rev.Stat. §211.071 (6) (1986).
[
Footnote 7]
The dissent believes that individualized consideration is no
solution, because
"the Eighth Amendment requires that a person who lacks that full
degree of responsibility for his or her actions associated with
adulthood not be sentenced to death,"
and this absolute cannot be assured if
"a juvenile offender's level of responsibility [is] taken into
account only along with a host of other factors that the court or
jury may decide outweigh that want of responsibility."
Post at
492 U. S. 397.
But it is equally true that individualized consideration will not
absolutely assure immunity from the death penalty to the
nonjuvenile who happens to be immature. If individualized
consideration is constitutionally inadequate, then the only logical
conclusion is that everyone is exempt from the death penalty.
JUSTICE O'CONNOR, concurring in part and concurring in the
judgment.
Last Term, in
Thompson v. Oklahoma, 487 U.
S. 815,
487 U. S.
857-858 (1988) (opinion concurring in judgment), I
expressed the view that a criminal defendant who would have been
tried as a juvenile under state law, but for the granting of a
petition waiving juvenile court jurisdiction, may only be executed
for a capital offense if the State's capital punishment statute
specifies a minimum age at which the commission of a capital crime
can lead to an offender's execution and the defendant had reached
that minimum age at the time the crime was committed. As a
threshold matter, I indicated that such specificity is not
necessary to avoid constitutional problems if it is clear that no
national consensus forbids the imposition of capital punishment for
crimes committed at such an age.
Id. at
487 U. S. 857.
Applying this two-part standard in
Thompson, I concluded
that Oklahoma's imposition of a death sentence on an individual who
was 15 years old at the time he committed a capital offense should
be set aside. Applying the same
Page 492 U. S. 381
standard today, I conclude that the death sentences for capital
murder imposed by Missouri and Kentucky on petitioners Wilkins and
Stanford respectively should not be set aside, because it is
sufficiently clear that no national consensus forbids the
imposition of capital punishment on 16- or 17-year-old capital
murderers.
In
Thompson, I noted that
"[t]he most salient statistic that bears on this case is that
every single American legislature that has expressly set a minimum
age for capital punishment has set that age at 16 or above."
Id. at
487 U. S. 849.
It is this difference between
Thompson and these cases,
more than any other, that convinces me there is no national
consensus forbidding the imposition of capital punishment for
crimes committed at the age of 16 and older.
See ante at
492 U. S.
370-372. As the Court indicates, "a majority of the
States that permit capital punishment authorize it for crimes
committed at age 16 or above. . . ."
Ante at
492 U. S. 371.
Three States, including Kentucky, have specifically set the minimum
age for capital punishment at 16,
see Ind.Code
§35-50-2-3(b) (1988); Ky.Rev.Stat.Ann. §640.040(1)
(Baldwin 1987); Nev.Rev.Stat. §176.025 (1987), and a fourth,
Florida, clearly contemplates the imposition of capital punishment
on 16-year-olds in its juvenile transfer statute,
see
Fla.Stat. §39.02(5)(c) (1987). Under these circumstances,
unlike the "peculiar circumstances" at work in
Thompson, I
do not think it necessary to require a state legislature to specify
that the commission of a capital crime can lead to the execution of
a 16- or 17-year-old offender. Because it is sufficiently clear
that today no national consensus forbids the imposition of capital
punishment in these circumstances, "the implicit nature of the
[Missouri] Legislature's decision [is] not . . . constitutionally
problematic." 487 U.S. at
487 U. S. 857.
This is true,
a fortiori, in the case of Kentucky, which
has specified 16 as the minimum age for the imposition of the death
penalty. The day may come when there is such general legislative
rejection of the execution of 16- or 17-year-old capital murderers
that a clear national
Page 492 U. S. 382
consensus can be said to have developed. Because I do not
believe that day has yet arrived, I concur in Parts I, II, III, and
IV-A of the Court's opinion, and I concur in its judgment.
I am unable, however, to join the remainder of the plurality's
opinion for reasons I stated in
Thompson. 492 U.
S. "
ante at
492 U. S. 378,
the suggestion that, beyond an assessment of the specific
enactments of American legislatures, there remains a constitutional
obligation imposed upon this Court to judge whether the "
nexus
between the punishment imposed and the defendant's
blameworthiness'" is proportional. Thompson, supra at
487 U. S. 853,
quoting Enmund v. Florida, 458 U.
S. 782, 458 U. S. 825
(1982) (O'CONNOR, J., dissenting). 492 U. S. In
my view, this Court does have a constitutional obligation to
conduct proportionality analysis. See Penry v. Lynaugh,
ante at 492 U. S.
335-340; Tison v. Arizona, 481 U.
S. 137, 481 U. S.
155-158 (1987); Enmund, 458 U.S. at
458 U. S.
797-801; id. at 458 U. S.
825-826 (O'CONNOR, J., dissenting). In
Thompson, I specifically identified age-based statutory
classifications as "relevant to Eighth Amendment proportionality
analysis." 487 U.S. at 487 U.S.
854 (opinion concurring in judgment). Thus, although I do
not believe that these particular cases can be resolved through
proportionality analysis, see Thompson, supra, at
487 U. S.
853-854, I reject the suggestion that the use of such
analysis is improper as a matter of Eighth Amendment jurisprudence.
Accordingly, I join all but Parts IV-B and V of the Court's
opinion.
JUSTICE BRENNAN, with whom JUSTICE MARSHALL, JUSTICE BLACKMUN,
and JUSTICE STEVENS join, dissenting.
I believe that to take the life of a person as punishment for a
crime committed when below the age of 18 is cruel and unusual, and
hence is prohibited by the Eighth Amendment.
Page 492 U. S. 383
The method by which this Court assesses a claim that a
punishment is unconstitutional because it is cruel and unusual is
established by our precedents, and it bears little resemblance to
the method four Members of the Court apply in this case. To be
sure, we begin the task of deciding whether a punishment is
unconstitutional by reviewing legislative enactments and the work
of sentencing juries relating to the punishment in question to
determine whether our Nation has set its face against a punishment
to an extent that it can be concluded that the punishment offends
our "evolving standards of decency."
Trop v. Dulles,
356 U. S. 86,
356 U. S. 101
(1958) (plurality opinion). The Court undertakes such an analysis
in this case.
Ante at
492 U. S.
370-373. But JUSTICE SCALIA, in his plurality opinion on
this point, ante, at 374-380, would treat the Eighth Amendment
inquiry as complete with this investigation. I agree with JUSTICE
O'CONNOR,
ante at
492 U. S. 382, that a more searching inquiry is mandated
by our precedents interpreting the Cruel and Unusual Punishments
Clause. In my view, that inquiry must in this case go beyond
age-based statutory classifications relating to matters other than
capital punishment,
cf. ante at
492 U. S. 382
(O'CONNOR, J., concurring in part and concurring in judgment), and
must also encompass what JUSTICE SCALIA calls, with evident but
misplaced disdain, "ethicoscientific" evidence. Only then can we be
in a position to judge, as our cases require, whether a punishment
is unconstitutionally excessive, either because it is
disproportionate, given the culpability of the offender, or because
it serves no legitimate penal goal.
I
Our judgment about the constitutionality of a punishment under
the Eighth Amendment is informed, though not determined,
see
infra at
492 U. S. 391,
by an examination of contemporary attitudes toward the punishment,
as evidenced in the actions of legislatures and of juries.
McCleskey v. Kemp, 481 U. S. 279,
481 U. S. 300
(1987);
Coker v. Georgia, 433 U.
S. 584,
433 U. S. 592
(1977)
Page 492 U. S. 384
(plurality opinion). The views of organizations with expertise
in relevant fields and the choices of governments elsewhere in the
world also merit our attention as indicators whether a punishment
is acceptable in a civilized society.
A
The Court's discussion of state laws concerning capital
sentencing,
ante at
492 U. S.
370-372, gives a distorted view of the evidence of
contemporary standards that these legislative determinations
provide. Currently, 12 of the States whose statutes permit capital
punishment specifically mandate that offenders under age 18 not be
sentenced to death.
Ante at
492 U. S.
370-371, n. 2. When one adds to these 12 States the 15
(including the District of Columbia) in which capital punishment is
not authorized at all, [
Footnote
2/1] it appears that the governments in fully 27 of the States
have concluded that no one under 18 should face the death penalty.
A further three States explicitly refuse to authorize sentences of
death for those who committed their offense when under 17,
ante at
492 U. S. 370,
n. 2, making a total of 30 States that would not tolerate the
execution of petitioner Wilkins. Congress' most recent enactment of
a death penalty statute also excludes those under 18.
Page 492 U. S. 385
Pub.L. 100-690, § 7001 (1), 102 Stat. 4390, 21 U.S.C.
§ 848(1) (1988 ed.).
In 19 States that have a death penalty, no minimum age for
capital sentences is set in the death penalty statute.
See
Thompson v. Oklahoma, 487 U. S. 815,
487 U. S.
826-827, and n. 26 (1988), and
492
U.S. 361fn2/1|>n. 1,
supra. The notion that these
States have consciously authorized the execution of juveniles
derives from the congruence in those jurisdictions of laws
permitting state courts to hand down death sentences, on the one
hand, and, on the other, statutes permitting the transfer of
offenders under 18 from the juvenile to state court systems for
trial in certain circumstances.
See Thompson, supra, at
487 U. S.
867-868, and n. 3 (SCALIA, J., dissenting). I would not
assume, however, in considering how the States stand on the moral
issue that underlies the constitutional question with which we are
presented, that a legislature that has never specifically
considered the issue has made a conscious moral choice to permit
the execution of juveniles.
See 487 U.S. at
487 U. S.
826-827, n. 24 (plurality opinion). O n a matter of such
moment that most States have expressed an explicit and contrary
judgment, the decisions of legislatures that are only implicit, and
that lack the "earmarks of careful consideration that we have
required for other kinds of decisions leading to the death
penalty,"
id. at
487 U. S. 857
(O'CONNOR, J., concurring in judgment), must count for little. I do
not suggest, of course, that laws of these States cut
against the constitutionality of the juvenile death
penalty -- only that accuracy demands that the baseline for our
deliberations should be that 27 States refuse to authorize a
sentence of death in the circumstances of petitioner Stanford's
case, and 30 would not permit Wilkins' execution; that 19 States
have not squarely faced the question; and that only the few
remaining jurisdictions have explicitly set an age below 18 at
which a person may be sentenced to death.
B
The application of these laws is another indicator the Court
agrees to be relevant. The fact that juries have on occasion
Page 492 U. S. 386
sentenced a minor to death shows, the Court says, that the death
penalty for adolescents is not categorically unacceptable to
juries.
Ante at
492 U. S. 374.
This, of course, is true; but it is not a conclusion that takes
Eighth Amendment analysis very far. Just as we have never insisted
that a punishment have been rejected unanimously by the States
before we may judge it cruel and unusual, so we have never adopted
the extraordinary view that a punishment is beyond Eighth Amendment
challenge if it is sometimes handed down by a jury.
See, e.g.,
Enmund v. Florida, 458 U. S. 782,
458 U. S. 792
(1982) (holding the death penalty cruel and unusual punishment for
participation in a felony in which an accomplice commits murder,
though about a third of American jurisdictions authorized such
punishment, and at least six nontriggerman felony murderers had
been executed, and three others were on death rows);
Coker v.
Georgia, 433 U. S. 584,
433 U. S.
596-597 (1977) (holding capital punishment
unconstitutional for the rape of an adult woman, though 72 persons
had been executed for rape in this country since 1955,
see
Enmund, supra, at
458 U. S. 795,
and though Georgia juries handed down six death sentences for rape
between 1973 and 1977).
Enmund and
Coker amply
demonstrate that it is no "requisite" of finding an Eighth
Amendment violation that the punishment in issue be "categorically
unacceptable to prosecutors and juries,"
ante at
492 U. S. 374
-- and, evidently, resort to the Cruel and Unusual Punishment
Clause would not be necessary to test a sentence never imposed
because categorically unacceptable to juries.
Both in absolute and in relative terms, imposition of the death
penalty on adolescents is distinctly unusual. Adolescent offenders
make up only a small proportion of the current death-row
population: 30 out of a total of 2,186 inmates, or 1.37 percent.
NAACP Legal Defense and Educational Fund, Inc. (LDF), Death Row,
U.S.A. (Mar. 1, 1989). [
Footnote
2/2]
Page 492 U. S. 387
Eleven minors were sentenced to die in 1982; 9 in 1983; 6 in
1984; 5 in 1985; 7 in 1986; and 2 in 1987. App. N to Brief for the
Office of the Capital Collateral Representative for the State of
Florida as
Amicus Curiae (hereafter OCCR Brief).
Forty-one, or 2.3 percent, of the 1,813 death sentences imposed
between January 1, 1982, and June 30, 1988, were for juvenile
crimes.
Id. at 15, and App.R. And juvenile offenders are
significantly less likely to receive the death penalty than adults.
During the same period, there were 97,086 arrests of adults for
homicide, and 1,772 adult death sentences, or 1.8 percent; and
8,911 arrests of minors for homicide, compared to 41 juvenile death
sentences, or 0.5 percent.
Ibid., and Apps. Q and R.
[
Footnote 2/3]
The Court speculates that this very small number of capital
sentences imposed on adolescents indicates that juries have
considered the youth of the offender when determining sentence, and
have reserved the punishment for rare cases in which it is
nevertheless appropriate.
Ante at
492 U. S. 374.
The State of Georgia made a very similar and equally conjectural
argument in
Coker -- that,
"as a practical matter, juries simply reserve the extreme
sanction for extreme cases of rape, and that recent experience . .
. does not prove that jurors consider the death penalty to be a
disproportionate punishment for every conceivable instance of
rape."
433 U.S. at
433 U. S. 597.
This Court, however, summarily rejected this claim, noting simply
that, in the vast majority of cases, Georgia juries had not imposed
the death sentence for rape. It is certainly true that, in the vast
majority of cases, juries have not sentenced juveniles to death,
and it seems to me perfectly proper to conclude that a sentence so
rarely imposed is "unusual."
Page 492 U. S. 388
C
Further indicators of contemporary standards of decency that
should inform our consideration of the Eighth Amendment question
are the opinions of respected organizations.
Thompson, 487
U.S. at
487 U. S. 830
(plurality opinion). Where organizations with expertise in a
relevant area have given careful consideration to the question of a
punishment's appropriateness, there is no reason why that judgment
should not be entitled to attention as an indicator of contemporary
standards. There is no dearth of opinion from such groups that the
state-sanctioned killing of minors is unjustified. A number,
indeed, have filed briefs
amicus curiae in these cases, in
support of petitioners. [
Footnote
2/4] The American Bar Association has adopted a resolution
opposing the imposition of capital punishment upon any person for
an offense committed while under age 18, [
Footnote 2/5] as has the National Council of
Juvenile
Page 492 U. S. 389
and Family Court Judges. [
Footnote
2/6] The American Law Institute's Model Penal Code similarly
includes a lower age limit of 18 for the death sentence. [
Footnote 2/7] And the National Commission
on Reform of the Federal Criminal Laws also recommended that 18 be
the minimum age. [
Footnote 2/8]
Our cases recognize that objective indicators of contemporary
standards of decency in the form of legislation in other countries
is also of relevance to Eighth Amendment analysis.
Thompson,
supra, at
487 U. S.
830-831;
Enmund, 458 U.S. at
458 U. S. 796,
n. 22;
Coker, 433 U.S. at
433 U. S. 596,
n. 10;
Trop v. Dulles, 356 U.S. at
356 U. S. 102,
and n. 35. Many countries, of course -- over 50, including nearly
all in Western Europe -- have formally abolished the death penalty,
or have limited its use to exceptional crimes such as treason. App.
to Brief for Amnesty International as
Amicus Curiae.
Twenty-seven others do not in practice impose the penalty.
Ibid. Of the nations that retain capital punishment, a
majority -- 65 -- prohibit the execution of juveniles.
Ibid. Sixty-one countries retain capital punishment and
have no statutory provision exempting juveniles, though some of
these nations are ratifiers of international treaties that do
prohibit the execution of juveniles.
Ibid. Since 1979,
Amnesty International has recorded only eight executions of
offenders under 18 throughout the world, three of these in the
United States. The other five executions were carried out in
Pakistan, Bangladesh, Rwanda, and Barbados. [
Footnote 2/9] In addition to national laws, three
leading human rights treaties ratified or signed by the United
States
Page 492 U. S. 390
explicitly prohibit juvenile death penalties. [
Footnote 2/10] Within the world community, the
imposition of the death penalty for juvenile crimes appears to be
overwhelmingly disapproved.
D
Together, the rejection of the death penalty for juveniles by a
majority of the States, the rarity of the sentence for juveniles,
both as an absolute and a comparative matter, the decisions of
respected organizations in relevant fields that this punishment is
unacceptable, and its rejection generally throughout the world,
provide to my mind a strong grounding for the view that it is not
constitutionally tolerable that certain States persist in
authorizing the execution of adolescent offenders. It is
unnecessary, however, to rest a view that the Eighth Amendment
prohibits the execution of minors solely upon a judgment as to the
meaning to be attached to the evidence of contemporary values
outlined above, for the execution of juveniles fails to satisfy two
well-established and independent Eighth Amendment requirements --
that a
Page 492 U. S. 391
punishment not be disproportionate, and that it make a
contribution to acceptable goals of punishment.
II
JUSTICE SCALIA forthrightly states in his plurality opinion that
Eighth Amendment analysis is at an end once legislation and jury
verdicts relating to the punishment in question are analyzed as
indicators of contemporary values. A majority of the Court rejected
this revisionist view as recently as last Term,
see
Thompson, 487 U.S. at
487 U. S. 833-838 (plurality opinion);
id. at
487 U. S.
853-854 (opinion of O'CONNOR, J.), and does so again in
this case and in Penry v. Lynaugh,
ante p.
492 U. S. 302. We
need not and should not treat this narrow range of factors as
determinative of our decision whether a punishment violates the
Constitution because it is excessive.
The Court has explicitly stated that "the attitude of state
legislatures and sentencing juries
do not wholly
determine" a controversy arising under the Eighth Amendment,
Coker, 433 U.S. at
433 U. S. 597
(plurality opinion) (emphasis added), because
"the Constitution contemplates that, in the end, our own
judgment will be brought to bear on the question of the
[constitutional] acceptability of"
a punishment,
ibid. See also id. at
433 U. S.
603-604, n. 2 (Powell, J., concurring in judgment)
("[T]he ultimate decision as to the appropriateness of the death
penalty under the Eighth Amendment . . . must be decided on the
basis of our own judgment in light of the precedents of this
Court");
Enmund, 458 U.S. at
458 U. S. 797
("Although the judgments of legislatures, juries, and prosecutors
weigh heavily in the balance, it is for us ultimately to judge
whether the Eighth Amendment permits imposition of the death
penalty" in a particular class of cases).
JUSTICE SCALIA's approach would largely return the task of
defining the contours of Eighth Amendment protection to political
majorities. But
"[t]he very purpose of a Bill of Rights was to withdraw certain
subjects from the vicissitudes of political controversy, to place
them beyond the reach of majorities and
Page 492 U. S. 392
officials and to establish them as legal principles to be
applied by the courts. One's right to life, liberty, and property,
to free speech, a free press, freedom of worship and assembly, and
other fundamental rights may not be submitted to vote; they depend
on the outcome of no elections."
West Virginia Board of Education v. Barnette,
319 U. S. 624,
319 U. S. 638
(1943).
Compare ante at
492 U. S.
375-377,
with Whitley v. Albers, 475 U.
S. 312,
475 U. S. 318
(1986) ("The language of the Eighth Amendment . . . manifests
an intention to limit the power of those entrusted with the
criminal-law function of government'"). The promise of the Bill of
Rights goes unfulfilled when we leave "[c]onstitutional doctrine
[to] be formulated by the acts of those institutions which the
Constitution is supposed to limit," Radin, The Jurisprudence of
Death, 126 U.Pa.L.Rev. 989, 1036 (1978), as is the case under
JUSTICE SCALIA's positivist approach to the definition of citizens'
rights. This Court abandons its proven and proper role in our
constitutional system when it hands back to the very majorities the
Framers distrusted the power to define the precise scope of
protection afforded by the Bill of Rights, rather than bringing its
own judgment to bear on that question, after complete analysis.
Despite JUSTICE SCALIA's view to the contrary, however,
"our cases . . . make clear that public perceptions of standards
of decency with respect to criminal sanctions are not conclusive. A
penalty also must accord with 'the dignity of man,' which is the
'basic concept underlying the Eighth Amendment.' . . . This means,
at least, that the punishment not be 'excessive.' . . . [T]he
inquiry into 'excessiveness' has two aspects. First, the punishment
must not involve the unnecessary and wanton infliction of pain. . .
. Second, the punishment must not be grossly out of proportion to
the severity of the crime."
Gregg v. Georgia, 428 U. S. 153,
428 U. S. 173
(1976) (opinion of Stewart, Powell, and STEVENS, JJ.).
Page 492 U. S. 393
Thus, in addition to asking whether legislative or jury
rejection of a penalty shows that "society has set its face against
it,"
ante at
492 U. S. 378,
the Court asks whether "a punishment is
excessive' and
unconstitutional" because there is disproportion "between the
punishment imposed and the defendant's blameworthiness,"
ante at 492 U. S. 382
(opinion of O'CONNOR, J.), or because it
"makes no measurable contribution to acceptable goals of
punishment, and hence is nothing more than the purposeless and
needless imposition of pain and suffering,"
Coker, supra, at
433 U. S. 592
(plurality opinion).
See, e.g., Penry, ante at
492 U. S. 335
(opinion of O'CONNOR, J.);
ante at
492 U. S.
342-343 (BRENNAN, J., concurring in part and dissenting
in part).
III
There can be no doubt at this point in our constitutional
history that the Eighth Amendment forbids punishment that is wholly
disproportionate to the blameworthiness of the offender. "The
constitutional principle of proportionality has been recognized
explicitly in this Court for almost a century."
Solem v.
Helm, 463 U. S. 277,
463 U. S. 286
(1983). Usually formulated as a requirement that sentences not be
"disproportionate to the crime committed,"
id., at
463 U. S. 284;
see, e.g., Weems v. United States, 217 U.
S. 349 (1910);
O'Neil v. Vermont, 144 U.
S. 323, 339-340 (1892) (Field, J., dissenting), the
proportionality principle takes account not only of the "injury to
the person and to the public" caused by a crime, but also of the
"moral depravity" of the offender.
Coker, supra, at
433 U. S. 598.
The offender's culpability for his criminal acts -- "the degree of
the defendant's blameworthiness,"
Enmund, supra, at
458 U. S. 815
(O'CONNOR, J., dissenting);
see also id. at
458 U. S. 798
(opinion of the Court) -- is thus of central importance to the
constitutionality of the sentence imposed. Indeed, this focus on a
defendant's blameworthiness runs throughout our constitutional
jurisprudence relating to capital sentencing.
See, e.g., Booth
v. Maryland, 482 U. S. 496,
482 U. S. 502
(1987) (striking down state statute requiring consideration by
sentencer of evidence other than defendant's record and
characteristics and the circumstances
Page 492 U. S. 394
of the crime, which had no "bearing on the defendant's
personal responsibility and moral guilt'"); California v.
Brown, 479 U. S. 538,
479 U. S. 545
(1987) (an "emphasis on culpability in sentencing decisions has
long been reflected in Anglo-American jurisprudence. . . .
Lockett and Eddings reflect the belief that
punishment should be directly related to the personal culpability
of the criminal defendant") (O'CONNOR, J., concurring).
Proportionality analysis requires that we compare "the gravity
of the offense," understood to include not only the injury caused,
but also the defendant's culpability, with "the harshness of the
penalty."
Solem, supra, at
463 U. S. 292.
In my view, juveniles so generally lack the degree of
responsibility for their crimes that is a predicate for the
constitutional imposition of the death penalty that the Eighth
Amendment forbids that they receive that punishment.
A
Legislative determinations distinguishing juveniles from adults
abound. These age-based classifications reveal much about how our
society regards juveniles as a class, and about societal beliefs
regarding adolescent levels of responsibility.
See
Thompson, 487 U.S. at
487 U. S. 823-825 (plurality opinion).
The participation of juveniles in a substantial number of
activities open to adults is either barred completely or
significantly restricted by legislation. All States but two have a
uniform age of majority, and have set that age at 18 or above. OCCR
Brief, App. A. No State has lowered its voting age below 18.
Id., App. C;
see Thompson, supra, at
487 U. S. 839,
App. A. Nor does any State permit a person under 18 to serve on a
jury. OCCR Brief, App. B;
see Thompson, supra, at 840,
App. B. Only four States ever permit persons below 18 to marry
without parental consent. OCCR Brief, App. D;
see Thompson,
supra, at
487 U. S. 843,
App. D. Thirty-seven States have specific enactments requiring that
a patient have attained 18 before she may validly consent to
medical treatment. OCCR Brief, App. E. Thirty-four
Page 492 U. S. 395
States require parental consent before a person below 18 may
drive a motor car.
Id., App. F;
see Thompson,
supra, at
487 U. S. 842,
App. C. Legislation in 42 States prohibits those under 18 from
purchasing pornographic materials. OCCR Brief, App. G;
see
Thompson, supra, at
487 U. S. 845,
App. E. Where gambling is legal, adolescents under 18 are generally
not permitted to participate in it, in some or all of its forms.
OCCR Brief, App. H;
see Thompson, supra, at
487 U. S. 847,
App. F. In these and a host of other ways, minors are treated
differently from adults in our laws, which reflects the simple
truth derived from communal experience that juveniles, as a class,
have not the level of maturation and responsibility that we presume
in adults and consider desirable for full participation in the
rights and duties of modern life.
"The reasons why juveniles are not trusted with the privileges
and responsibilities of an adult also explain why their
irresponsible conduct is not as morally reprehensible as that of an
adult."
Thompson, supra, at
487 U. S. 835
(plurality opinion). Adolescents "are more vulnerable, more
impulsive, and less self-disciplined than adults," and are without
the same "capacity to control their conduct and to think in
long-range terms." Twentieth Century Fund Task Force on Sentencing
Policy Toward Young Offenders, Confronting Youth Crime 7 (1978)
(hereafter Task Force). They are particularly impressionable and
subject to peer pressure,
see Eddings v. Oklahoma,
455 U. S. 104,
455 U. S. 115
(1982), and prone to "experiment, risk-taking and bravado," Task
Force 3. They lack "experience, perspective, and judgment."
Bellotti v. Baird, 443 U. S. 622,
443 U. S. 635
(1979).
See generally Thompson, supra, at
487 U. S.
843-844, n. 43; Brief for American Society for
Adolescent Psychiatry
et al. as Amici Curiae (reviewing
scientific evidence). Moreover, the very paternalism that our
society shows toward youths and the dependency it forces upon them
mean that society bears a responsibility for the actions of
juveniles that it does not for the actions of adults who are, at
least theoretically, free to make their own choices:
"youth crime . . . is not exclusively the offender's fault;
offenses by
Page 492 U. S. 396
the young represent a failure of family, school, and the social
system, which share responsibility for the development of America's
youth."
Task Force 7.
To be sure, the development of cognitive and reasoning abilities
and of empathy, the acquisition of experience upon which these
abilities operate and upon which the capacity to make sound value
judgments depends, and in general the process of maturation into a
self-directed individual fully responsible for his or her actions,
occur by degrees.
See, e.g., G. Manaster, Adolescent
Development and the Life Tasks (1977). But the factors discussed
above indicate that 18 is the dividing line that society has
generally drawn, the point at which it is thought reasonable to
assume that persons have an ability to make, and a duty to bear
responsibility for their, judgments. Insofar as age 18 is a
necessarily arbitrary social choice as a point at which to
acknowledge a person's maturity and responsibility, given the
different developmental rates of individuals, it is, in fact,
"a conservative estimate of the dividing line between
adolescence and adulthood. Many of the psychological and emotional
changes that an adolescent experiences in maturing do not actually
occur until the early 20s."
Brief for American Society for Adolescent Psychiatry
et
al. as
Amici Curiae 4 (citing social scientific
studies).
B
There may be exceptional individuals who mature more quickly
than their peers, and who might be considered fully responsible for
their actions prior to the age of 18, despite their lack of the
experience upon which judgment depends. [
Footnote 2/11] In my view, however, it is not
sufficient to accommodate the
Page 492 U. S. 397
facts about juveniles that an individual youth's culpability may
be taken into account in the decision to transfer him or her from
the juvenile to the adult court system for trial, or that a capital
sentencing jury is instructed to consider youth and other
mitigating factors. I believe that the Eighth Amendment requires
that a person who lacks that full degree of responsibility for his
or her actions associated with adulthood not be sentenced to death.
Hence it is constitutionally inadequate that a juvenile offender's
level of responsibility be taken into account only along with a
host of other factors that the court or jury may decide outweigh
that want of responsibility.
Immaturity that constitutionally should operate as a bar to a
disproportionate death sentence does not guarantee that a minor
will not be transferred for trial to the adult court system.
Rather, the most important considerations in the decision to
transfer a juvenile offender are the seriousness of the offense,
the extent of prior delinquency, and the response to prior
treatment within the juvenile justice system. National Institute
for Juvenile Justice and Delinquency, United States Dept. of
Justice, Major Issues in Juvenile Justice Information and Training,
Youth in Adult Courts: Between Two Worlds 211 (1982).
Psychological, intellectual, and other personal characteristics of
juvenile offenders receive little attention at the transfer stage,
and cannot account for differences between those transferred and
those who remain in the juvenile court system.
See Solway,
Hays, Schreiner, & Cansler, Clinical Study of Youths Petitioned
for Certification as Adults, 46 Psychological Rep. 1067 (1980). Nor
is an adolescent's lack of full culpability isolated at the
sentencing stage as a factor that determinatively bars a death
sentence. A jury is free to weigh a juvenile offender's youth and
lack of full responsibility against the heinousness of the crime
and other aggravating factors -- and, finding the aggravating
factors weightier, to sentence even the most immature of 16- or
17-year olds to be killed. By no stretch of the imagination,
Page 492 U. S. 398
then, are the transfer and sentencing decisions designed to
isolate those juvenile offenders who are exceptionally mature and
responsible, and who thus stand out from their peers as a
class.
It is thus unsurprising that individualized consideration at
transfer and sentencing has not in fact ensured that juvenile
offenders lacking an adult's culpability are not sentenced to die.
Quite the contrary. Adolescents on death row appear typically to
have a battery of psychological, emotional, and other problems
going to their likely capacity for judgment and level of
blameworthiness. A recent diagnostic evaluation of all 14 juveniles
on death rows in four States is instructive. Lewis
et al.,
Neuropsychiatric, Psychoeducational, and Family Characteristics of
14 Juveniles Condemned to Death in the United States, 145
Am.J.Psychiatry 584 (1988). Seven of the adolescents sentenced to
die were psychotic when evaluated, or had been so diagnosed in
earlier childhood; four others had histories consistent with
diagnoses of severe mood disorders; and the remaining three
experienced periodic paranoid episodes, during which they would
assault perceived enemies.
Id. at 585, and Table 3. Eight
had suffered severe head injuries during childhood,
id. at
585, and Table 1, and nine suffered from neurological
abnormalities,
id. at 585, and Table 2. Psychoeducational
testing showed that only 2 of these death-row inmates had IQ scores
above 90 (that is, in the normal range) -- and both individuals
suffered from psychiatric disorders -- while 10 offenders showed
impaired abstract reasoning on at least some tests.
Id. at
585-586, and Tables 3 and 4. All but two of the adolescents had
been physically abused, and five sexually abused.
Id. at
586-587, and Table 5. Within the families of these children,
violence, alcoholism, drug abuse, and psychiatric disorders were
commonplace.
Id. at 587, and Table 5.
The cases under consideration today certainly do not suggest
that individualized consideration at transfer and sentencing
Page 492 U. S. 399
ensure that only exceptionally mature juveniles, as blameworthy
for their crimes as an adult, are sentenced to death. Transferring
jurisdiction over Kevin Stanford to Circuit Court, the Juvenile
Division of the Jefferson, Kentucky, District Court nevertheless
found that Stanford, who was 17 at the time of his crime,
"has a low internalization of the values and morals of society
and lacks social skills. That he does possess an institutionalized
personality and has, in effect, because of his chaotic family life
and lack of treatment, become socialized in delinquent behavior.
That he is emotionally immature, and could be amenable to treatment
if properly done on a long-term basis of psychotherap[eu]tic
intervention and reality-based therapy for socialization and drug
therapy in a residential facility."
App. in No. 87-5765, p. 9.
At the penalty phase of Stanford's trial, witnesses testified
that Stanford, who lived with various relatives, had used drugs
from the age of about 13, and that his drug use had caused changes
in his personality and behavior. 10 Record in No. 87-5765, pp.
1383-1392, 1432. Stanford had been placed at times in juvenile
treatment facilities, and a witness who had assessed him upon his
admission to an employment skills project found that he lacked
age-appropriate social interaction skills; had a history of drug
abuse; and wanted for family support or supervision.
Id.
at 1408;
see also id. at 1440-1442.
Heath Wilkins was 16 when he committed the crime for which
Missouri intends to kill him. The juvenile court, in ordering him
transferred for trial to adult court, focused upon the viciousness
of Wilkins' crime, the juvenile system's inability to rehabilitate
him in the 17 months of juvenile confinement available, and the
need to protect the public, though it also mentioned that Wilkins
was, in its view, "an experienced person, and mature in his
appearance and habits." App. in No. 87-6026, p. 5. The Circuit
Court found Wilkins
Page 492 U. S. 400
competent to stand trial. [
Footnote 2/12] Record in No. 87-6026, p. 42. Wilkins
then waived counsel, with the avowed intention of pleading guilty
and seeking the death penalty,
id. at 42, 55, and the
Circuit Court accepted the waiver,
id. at 84, and later
Wilkins' guilty plea,
id. at 144-145. Wilkins was not
represented by counsel at sentencing.
See id. at 188-190.
Presenting no mitigating evidence, he told the court he would
prefer the death penalty to life in prison,
id. at 186-187
-- "[o]ne I fear, the other one I don't,"
id. at 295 --
and after hearing evidence from the State, the Court sentenced
Wilkins to die. Wilkins took no steps to appeal, and objected to an
amicus' efforts on his behalf. The Missouri Supreme Court, however,
ordered an evaluation to determine whether Wilkins was competent to
waive his right to appellate counsel. Concluding that Wilkins was
incompetent to waive his rights, [
Footnote 2/13] the state-appointed forensic
psychiatrist found that
!492 U.S. 401
Wilkins "suffers from a mental disorder" that affects his
"reasoning and impairs his behavior." App. in No. 87-6026, p. 74.
It would be incredible to suppose, given this psychiatrist's
conclusion and his summary of Wilkins' past, set out in the margin,
[
Footnote 2/14] that Missouri's
transfer and sentencing schemes
Page 492 U. S. 401
had operated to identify in Wilkins a 16-year old mature and
culpable beyond his years.
C
Juveniles very generally lack that degree of blameworthiness
that is, in my view, a constitutional prerequisite for the
Page 492 U. S. 402
imposition of capital punishment under our precedents concerning
the Eighth Amendment proportionality principle. The individualized
consideration of an offender's youth and culpability at the
transfer stage and at sentencing has not operated to ensure that
the only offenders under 18 singled out for the ultimate penalty
are exceptional individuals whose level of responsibility is more
developed than that of their peers. In that circumstance, I believe
that the same categorical assumption that juveniles as a class are
insufficiently mature to be regarded as fully responsible that we
make in so many other areas is appropriately made in determining
whether minors may be subjected to the death penalty. As we noted
in
Thompson, 487 U.S. at
487 U. S.
825-826, n. 23, it would be ironic if the assumptions we
so readily make about minors as a class were suddenly unavailable
in conducting proportionality analysis. I would hold that the
Eighth Amendment prohibits the execution of any person for a crime
committed below the age of 18.
IV
Under a second strand of Eighth Amendment inquiry into whether a
particular sentence is excessive, and hence unconstitutional, we
ask whether the sentence makes a measurable contribution to
acceptable goals of punishment.
Thompson, supra, at 833;
Enmund v. Florida, 458 U.S. at
458 U. S. 798;
Coker v. Georgia, 433 U.S. at
433 U. S. 592;
Gregg v. Georgia, 428 U.S. at
428 U. S. 173.
The two "principal social purposes" of capital punishment are said
to be "retribution and the deterrence of capital crimes by
prospective offenders."
Gregg, supra, at
428 U. S. 183;
see Enmund, supra, at
458 U. S. 798.
Unless the death penalty applied to persons for offenses committed
under 18 measurably contributes to one of these goals, the Eighth
Amendment prohibits it.
See ibid.
"[R]etribution as a justification for executing [offenders] very
much depends on the degree of [their] culpability."
Id. at
458 U. S. 800.
I have explained in
492 U. S.
supra, why I believe juveniles lack the culpability that
makes a crime so extreme
Page 492 U. S. 403
that it may warrant, according to this Court's cases, the death
penalty; and why we should treat juveniles as a class as exempt
from the ultimate penalty. These same considerations persuade me
that executing juveniles "does not measurably contribute to the
retributive end of ensuring that the criminal gets his just
deserts."
Id. at
458 U. S. 801.
See Thompson, supra, at
487 U. S.
836-837. A punishment that fails the Eighth Amendment
test of proportionality because disproportionate to the offender's
blameworthiness, by definition, is not justly deserved.
IV
Nor does the execution of juvenile offenders measurably
contribute to the goal of deterrence. Excluding juveniles from the
class of persons eligible to receive the death penalty will have
little effect on any deterrent value capital punishment may have
for potential offenders who are over 18: these adult offenders may
of course remain eligible for a death sentence. The potential
deterrent effect of juvenile executions on adolescent offenders is
also insignificant. The deterrent value of capital punishment
rests
"on the assumption that we are rational beings who always think
before we act, and then base our actions on a careful calculation
of the gains and losses involved."
Gardiner, The Purposes of Criminal Punishment, 21 Mod.L.Rev.
117, 122 (1958). As the plurality noted in
Thompson,
supra, at
487 U. S.
837,
"[t]he likelihood that the teenage offender has made the kind of
cost-benefit analysis that attaches any weight to the possibility
of execution is so remote as to be virtually nonexistent."
First, juveniles "have less capacity . . . to think in
long-range terms than adults," Task Force 7, and their careful
weighing of a distant, uncertain, and indeed highly unlikely
consequence prior to action is most improbable. [
Footnote 2/15] In addition, juveniles have
little
Page 492 U. S. 404
fear of death, because they have "a profound conviction of their
own omnipotence and immortality." Miller, Adolescent Suicide:
Etiology and Treatment, in 9 Adolescent Psychiatry 327, 329 (S.
Feinstein, J. Looney, A. Schwartzberg, & A. Sorosky eds. 1981).
See also, e.g., Gordon, The Tattered Cloak of Immortality,
in Adolescence and Death 16, 27 (C. Corr & J. McNeil eds. 1986)
(noting prevalence of adolescent risk-taking); Brief for American
Society for Adolescent Psychiatry
et al. as
Amici
Curiae 5-6 (citing research). Because imposition of the death
penalty on persons for offenses committed under the age of 18 makes
no measurable contribution to the goals of either retribution or
deterrence, it is "nothing more than the purposeless and needless
imposition of pain and suffering,"
Coker, supra, at
433 U. S. 592,
and is thus excessive and unconstitutional.
V
There are strong indications that the execution of juvenile
offenders violates contemporary standards of decency: a majority of
States decline to permit juveniles to be sentenced to death;
imposition of the sentence upon minors is very unusual even in
those States that permit it; and respected organizations with
expertise in relevant areas regard the execution of juveniles as
unacceptable, as does international opinion. These indicators serve
to confirm, in my view, my conclusion that the Eighth Amendment
prohibits the execution of persons for offenses they committed
while below the age of 18, because the death penalty is
disproportionate when applied to such young offenders and fails
measurably to serve the goals of capital punishment. I dissent.
[
Footnote 2/1]
See Thompson v. Oklahoma, 487 U.
S. 815,
487 U. S. 826,
and n. 25 (1988), listing 14 States. The 15th State to have
rejected capital punishment altogether is Vermont. Vermont repealed
a statute that had allowed capital punishment for some murders.
See Vt.Stat.Ann., Tit. 13, § 2303 (1974 and
Supp.1988). The State now provides for the death penalty only for
kidnaping with intent to extort money. § 2403. Insofar as it
permits a sentence of death, § 2403 was rendered
unconstitutional by our decision in
Furman v. Georgia,
408 U. S. 238
(1972), because Vermont's sentencing scheme does not guide jury
discretion,
see Vt.Stat.Ann., Tit. 13, §§
7101-7107 (1974). Vermont's decision not to amend its only law
allowing the death penalty in light of
Furman and its
progeny, in combination with its repeal of its statute permitting
capital punishment for murder, leads to the conclusion that the
State rejects capital punishment.
In addition, South Dakota, though it statutorily provides for a
death penalty, has sentenced no one to death since
Furman,
arguably making a 28th State that has abandoned the death
penalty.
[
Footnote 2/2]
One person currently on death row for juvenile crimes was
sentenced in Maryland, which has since set 18 as the minimum age
for its death penalty.
[
Footnote 2/3]
Capital sentences for juveniles would presumably be more unusual
still were capital juries drawn from a cross-section of our
society, rather than excluding many who oppose capital punishment,
see Lockhart v. McCree, 476 U. S. 162
(1986) -- a fact that renders capital jury sentences a distinctly
weighted measure of contemporary standards.
[
Footnote 2/4]
Briefs for American Bar Association; Child Welfare League of
America, National Parents and Teachers Association, National
Council on Crime and Delinquency, Children's Defense Fund, National
Association of Social Workers, National Black Child Development
Institute, National Network of Runaway and Youth Services, National
Youth Advocate Program, and American Youth Work Center; American
Society for Adolescent Psychiatry and American Orthopsychiatric
Association; Defense for Children International-USA; National Legal
Aid and Defender Association, and National Association of Criminal
Defense Lawyers; Office of Capital Collateral Representative for
the State of Florida; and International Human Rights Law Group, as
Amici Curiae. See also Briefs for American
Baptist Churches, American Friends Service Committee, American
Jewish Committee, American Jewish Congress, Christian Church
(Disciples of Christ), Mennonite Central Committee, General
Conference Mennonite Church, National Council of Churches, General
Assembly of the Presbyterian Church, Southern Christian Leadership
Conference, Union of American Hebrew Congregations, United Church
of Christ Commission for Racial Justice, United Methodist Church
General Board of Church and Society, and United States Catholic
Conference; West Virginia Council of Churches; and Amnesty
International as
Amici Curiae.
[
Footnote 2/5]
American Bar Association, Summary of Action of the House of
Delegates 17 (1983 Annual Meeting).
[
Footnote 2/6]
National Council of Juvenile and Family Court Judges, Juvenile
and Family Court Newsletter, Vol. 19, No. 1, p. 4 (Oct. 1988).
[
Footnote 2/7]
American Law Institute, Model Penal Code §210.6(1)(d)
(Proposed Official Draft 1962); American Law Institute, Model Penal
Code and Commentaries §210.6, Commentary, p. 133 (1980)
("[C]ivilized societies will not tolerate the spectacle of
execution of children").
[
Footnote 2/8]
National Commission on Reform of Federal Criminal Laws, Final
Report of the Proposed New Federal Criminal Code § 3603
(1971).
[
Footnote 2/9]
Brief for Amnesty International as
Amicus Curiae in
Thompson v. Oklahoma, O.T. 1987, No. 86-6169, p. 6.
[
Footnote 2/10]
Article 6(5) of the International Covenant on Civil and
Political Rights, Annex to G.A.Res. 2200, 21 U.N. GAOR Res.Supp.
(No. 16) 53, U.N.Doc. A/6316 (1966) (signed but not ratified by the
United States), reprinted in 6 International Legal Material 368,
370 (1967); Article 4(5) of the American Convention on Human
Rights, O.A.S. Official Records, OEA/Ser. K/XVI/1.1, Doc. 65, Rev.
1, Corr. 2 (1970) (same), reprinted in 9 International Legal
Material 673, 676 (1970); Article 68 of the Geneva Convention
Relative to the Protection of Civilian Persons in Time of War,
August 12, 1949, 6 U.S.T. 3516, T.I.A.S. No. 3365, (ratified by the
United States).
See also Resolutions and Decisions of the
United Nations Economic and Social Council, Res. 1984/50, U. N.
ESCOR Supp. (No. 1), p. 33, U. N. Doc. E/1984/84 (1984) (adopting
"safeguards guaranteeing protection of the rights of those facing
the death penalty," including the safeguard that "[p]ersons below
18 years of age at the time of the commission of the crime shall
not be sentenced to death"), endorsed by the United Nations General
Assembly, U.N. GAOR Res. 39/118, U.N.Doc. A/39/51, p. 211,
�� 2, 5 (1985), and adopted by the Seventh United
Nations Congress on the Prevention of Crime and the Treatment of
Offenders, p. 83, U.N.Doc. A/Conf. 121/22, U.N. Sales No. E.86.IV.1
(1986).
[
Footnote 2/11]
Delinquent juveniles are unlikely to be among these few.
Instead, they will typically be among those persons for whom
society's presumption of a capacity for mature judgment at 18 is
much too generous.
See, e.g., Scharf, Law and the Child's
Evolving Legal Conscience, in 1 Advances in Law and Child
Development 1, 16 (R. Sprague ed. 1982) (discussing study of
delinquents aged 15 to 17, suggesting that the group's mean moral
maturity level was below that of average middle-class 10- to
12-year-olds).
[
Footnote 2/12]
Two psychological reports were prepared concerning Wilkins when
the issue of his competency to stand trial arose. Neither suggests
that Wilkins was exceptionally mature for his age. One found his
intellectual functioning "within the average range," App. in No.
87-6026, p. 10, and his "[h]igher order processes," such as
reasoning and judgment, to be "within the approximate normal
range,"
id. at 11. The other concluded:
"[Wilkins'] capacity to manage and control affect is tenuous and
inconsistent, leaving him a subject to impulsive actions as well as
arbitrary and capricious thinking which is prone to skirt over
details, and considerations for logical systematic thought. He is
intolerant of intense affects such as anxiety, depression, or
anger, in that such feelings are overwhelming, interfere with his
ability to think clearly, and gives rise to impulsive action. He is
vulnerable to massive infusions of intense rage which leads to
spasms of destructive action. His rage commingles with a profound
depressive experience generated by an excruciating sense of lonely
alienation whereby he experiences both himself and other people as
being lifeless and empty. . . . "
"He barely experiences ties to others or emp[athe]tic attunement
. . . ."
Id. at 22.
[
Footnote 2/13]
Wilkins was diagnosed as being of a "Conduct Disorder,
Undersocialized-Aggressive Type," with a borderline personality
disorder that left him with
"difficulty in establishing a pattern of predictable response to
stressful situations vacillating between aggression towards others
or self-destructive activity."
Id. at 67-68. He had been "exhibiting bizarre behavior,
paranoid ideation, and idiosyncratic thinking" since 1982.
Id. at 68.
[
Footnote 2/14]
The state-appointed psychiatrist summarized Wilkins' past in his
report:
"Mr. Wilkins . . . was raised in a rather poor socioeconomic
environment [and] reportedly had extremely chaotic upbringing
during his childhood. He was physically abused by his mother,
sometimes the beatings would last for two hours. . . . As a child,
he started robbing houses for knives and money, and loved to set
fires. Mr. Wilkins' mother worked at night and slept during the
day, thus the children were left alone at night by themselves. He
claims that he was started on drugs by his uncle [at age six;
see id. at 67]. Apparently he used to shoot BB guns at
passing cars. Mr. Wilkins indicated that his mother's boyfriend had
a quick temper, and that he hated him. He also started disliking
his mother, not only because she punished [him], but also because
she stood up for her boyfriend, who was unkind towards [him]. He
then decided to poison his mother and boyfriend by placing rat
poison in Tylenol capsules. They were informed by his brother about
the situation. They secretly emptied the capsules and made him eat
them. He was afraid of death, and attempted vomiting by placing
[his] fingers in his throat. Then he ended up getting a beating
from his mother and boyfriend. At the age of ten, Mr. Wilkins was
evaluated at Tri-County Mental Health Center and Western Missouri
Mental Health Center. He stayed there for a period of six months.
He was then sent to Butterfield Youth's Home, and then to East
Range, a residential facility for boys. He started using drugs
quite heavily. . . . He also started drinking hard liquor . . . .
"
"At Butterfield, he was very angry at the teachers because they
considered him to be 'dumb.' He showed rather strange behavior
there. When he became depressed, he would dance with a net over his
head. On another occasion, he cut his wrist and claimed to have had
frequent thoughts of suicide. Prior to going to Butterfield, he had
jumped off a bridge but the car swerved before he was hit. At
Butterfield, he attempted to overdose with alcohol and drugs, and
another time with antipsychotic medication, Mellaril. Mr. Wilkins
was placed on Mellaril because he was 'too active.' He stayed at .
. . Butterfield . . . for three and one half years between the ages
of 10 through 13 1/2. After that, he was transferred to Crittenton
Center, since it was closer to his mother's residence. He stayed
there only for four or five months, and was then kicked out. The
court gave him permission to go home on probation. At this time,
his mother had started seeing another boyfriend, and Mr. Wilkins
apparently liked him. He continued the usage of alcohol and drugs
while at school, continued to break into houses stealing money,
jewelry, and knives, and generally stole money to spend at the
arcade. On one occasion, he ran away to Southern California. He was
introduced to amphetamines there, and spent all his money. . . .
After his return [home, he] was charged with a stolen knife and was
sent to [a] Detention Center . . . . At age 15, he was sent to the
Northwest Regional Youth Services in Kansas City. There, an attempt
at prescribing Thorazine (major tranquilizer) was made. After this,
Mr. Wilkins was placed in a foster home. He ran away from the
foster home . . . . Beginning in May of 1985, he lived on the
streets . . . . "
"
* * * *"
"Records from Butterfield . . . indicated that Mr. Wilkins'
natural father was committed to a mental institution in Arkansas,
and there was considerable amount of physical abuse that existed in
the family. . . . In the educational testing, he gave rather
unusual responses. For example, when asked the reasons why we need
policemen, he replied, 'To get rid of people like me.' He also
revealed plans to blow up a large building in Kansas City [and]
made bizarre derogatory sexual comments towards women prior to
visits with his mother. He had episodes of hyperventilation, and
passed out by fainting or chest squeezing. . . . On one occasion in
September of 1981, he put gasoline into a toilet and set fire to
it, causing an explosion. Mr. Wilkins' brother was diagnosed to be
suffering from schizophrenia when he was admitted along with Mr.
Wilkins in 1982 at Crittenton Center. Mr. Wilkins was often noticed
to be fantasizing about outer space and supernatural powers. In the
fall of 1982, [the Crittenton psychiatrist] recommended placement
on Mellaril because of a 'disoriented thinking pattern and high
anxiety.' In 1983, his condition started deteriorating. . . . His
final diagnoses in November of 1983, when he was discharged from
Crittenton, were Borderline Personality and Passive-Aggressive
Personality. Psychological testing at Crittenton indicated isolated
episodes of paranoid functioning."
Id. at 57-61.
[
Footnote 2/15]
See, e.g., Kastenbaum, Time and Death in Adolescence,
in The Meaning of Death 99, 104 (H. Feifel ed. 1959). Among the
conclusions Kastenbaum drew from his study were that
"[t]he adolescent lives in an intense present; 'now' is so real
to him that both past and future seem pallid by comparison.
Everything that is important and valuable in life lies either in
the immediate life situation or in the rather close future."
Ibid.