Petitioner credit reporting agency sent a report to five
subscribers indicating that respondent construction contractor had
filed a voluntary petition for bankruptcy. The report was false,
and grossly misrepresented respondent's assets and liabilities.
Thereafter, petitioner issued a corrective notice, but respondent
was dissatisfied with this notice and brought a defamation action
in Vermont state court, alleging that the false report had injured
its reputation and seeking damages. After trial, the jury returned
a verdict in respondent's favor and awarded both compensatory or
presumed damages and punitive damages. But the trial court believed
that
Gertz v. Robert Welch, Inc., 418 U.
S. 323, controlled, and granted petitioner's motion for
a new trial on the ground that the instructions to the jury
permitted it to award damages on a lesser showing than "actual
malice." The Vermont Supreme Court reversed, holding that
Gertz was inapplicable to nonmedia defamation actions.
Held: The judgment is affirmed.
143 Vt. 66,
461 A.2d 414,
affirmed.
JUSTICE POWELL, joined by JUSTICE REHNQUIST and JUSTICE
O'CONNOR, concluded that:
1. The fact that the jury instructions in question referred to
"malice," "lack of good faith," and "actual malice," did not
require the jury to find "actual malice," as respondent contends,
where the instructions failed to define any of these terms.
Consequently, the trial court correctly concluded that the
instructions did not satisfy
Gertz. Pp.
472 U. S.
753-755.
2. Permitting recovery of presumed and punitive damages in
defamation cases absent a showing of "actual malice" does not
violate the First Amendment when the defamatory statements do not
involve matters of public concern. Pp.
472 U. S.
755-763.
(a) In light of the reduced constitutional value of speech on
matters of purely private concern, as opposed to speech on matters
of public concern, the state interest in compensating private
individuals for injury to their reputation adequately supports
awards of presumed and punitive damages -- even absent a showing of
"actual malice."
Cf. Gertz. Pp.
472 U. S.
755-761.
(b)
Gertz, supra, does not apply to this case.
Petitioner's credit report concerned no public issue but was speech
solely in the individual
Page 472 U. S. 750
interest of the speaker and its specific business audience. This
particular interest warranted no special protection when it was
wholly false and damaging to the victim's business reputation.
Moreover, since the credit report was made available to only five
subscribers, who, under the subscription agreement, could not
disseminate it further, it cannot be said that the report involved
any strong interest in the free flow of commercial information. And
the speech here, like advertising, being solely motivated by a
desire for profit, is hardy and unlikely to be deterred by
incidental state regulation. In any event, the market provides a
powerful incentive to a credit reporting agency to be accurate,
since false reporting is of no use to creditors. Pp.
472 U. S.
761-763.
THE CHIEF JUSTICE concluded that
Gertz is inapplicable
to this case, because the allegedly defamatory expression involved
did not relate to a matter of public concern, and that no other
reason was needed to dispose of the case. Pp.
472 U. S.
763-764.
JUSTICE WHITE concluded that
Gertz should not be
applied to this case either because
Gertz should be
overruled or because the defamatory publication in question did not
deal with a matter of public importance. P.
472 U. S.
774.
POWELL, J., announced the judgment of the Court and delivered an
opinion, in which REHNQUIST and O'CONNOR, JJ., joined. BURGER,
C.J.,
post, p.
472 U. S. 763,
and WHITE, J.,
post, p.
472 U. S. 765,
filed opinions concurring in the judgment. BRENNAN, J., filed a
dissenting opinion, in which MARSHALL, BLACKMUN, and STEVENS, JJ.,
joined,
post, p.
472 U. S.
774.
Page 472 U. S. 751
JUSTICE POWELL announced the judgment of the Court and delivered
an opinion, in which JUSTICE REHNQUIST and JUSTICE O'CONNOR
joined.
In
Gertz v. Robert Welch, Inc., 418 U.
S. 323 (1974), we held that the First Amendment
restricted the damages that a private individual could obtain from
a publisher for a libel that involved a matter of public concern.
More specifically, we held that in these circumstances the First
Amendment prohibited awards of presumed and punitive damages for
false and defamatory statements unless the plaintiff shows "actual
malice," that is, knowledge of falsity or reckless disregard for
the truth. The question presented in this case is whether this rule
of
Gertz applies when the false and defamatory statements
do not involve matters of public concern.
I
Petitioner Dun & Bradstreet, a credit reporting agency,
provides subscribers with financial and related information about
businesses. All the information is confidential; under the terms of
the subscription agreement the subscribers may not reveal it to
anyone else. On July 26, 1976, petitioner sent a report to five
subscribers indicating that respondent, a construction contractor,
had filed a voluntary petition for bankruptcy. This report was
false and grossly misrepresented respondent's assets and
liabilities. That same day, while discussing the possibility of
future financing with its bank, respondent's president was told
that the bank had received the defamatory report. He immediately
called petitioner's regional office, explained the error, and asked
for a correction. In addition, he requested the names of the firms
that had received the false report in order to assure them that the
company was solvent. Petitioner promised to look into the matter,
but refused to divulge the names of those who had received the
report.
After determining that its report was indeed false, petitioner
issued a corrective notice on or about August 3, 1976,
Page 472 U. S. 752
to the five subscribers who had received the initial report. The
notice stated that one of respondent's former employees, not
respondent itself, had filed for bankruptcy, and that respondent
"continued in business as usual." Respondent told petitioner that
it was dissatisfied with the notice, and it again asked for a list
of subscribers who had seen the initial report. Again petitioner
refused to divulge their names.
Respondent then brought this defamation action in Vermont state
court. It alleged that the false report had injured its reputation
and sought both compensatory and punitive damages. The trial
established that the error in petitioner's report had been caused
when one of its employees, a 17-year-old high school student paid
to review Vermont bankruptcy pleadings, had inadvertently
attributed to respondent a bankruptcy petition filed by one of
respondent's former employees. Although petitioner's representative
testified that it was routine practice to check the accuracy of
such reports with the businesses themselves, it did not try to
verify the information about respondent before reporting it.
After trial, the jury returned a verdict in favor of respondent
and awarded $50,000 in compensatory or presumed damages and
$300,000 in punitive damages. Petitioner moved for a new trial. It
argued that, in
Gertz v. Robert Welch, Inc., supra, at
418 U. S. 349,
this Court had ruled broadly that
"the States may not permit recovery of presumed or punitive
damages, at least when liability is not based on a showing of
knowledge of falsity or reckless disregard for the truth,"
and it argued that the judge's instructions in this case
permitted the jury to award such damages on a lesser showing. The
trial court indicated some doubt as to whether
Gertz
applied to "non-media cases," but granted a new trial "[b]ecause of
. . . dissatisfaction with its charge and . . . conviction that the
interests of justice require[d]" it. App. 26.
The Vermont Supreme Court reversed. 143 Vt. 66,
461 A.2d 414
(1983). Although recognizing that "in certain instances, the
distinction between media and nonmedia defendants
Page 472 U. S. 753
may be difficult to draw," the court stated that
"no such difficulty is presented with credit reporting agencies,
which are in the business of selling financial information to a
limited number of subscribers who have paid substantial fees for
their services."
Id. at 73, 461 A.2d at 417. Relying on this
distinguishing characteristic of credit reporting firms, the court
concluded that such firms are not "the type of media worthy of
First Amendment protection as contemplated by
New York
Times \[Co. v. Sullivan, 376 U.
S. 254 (1964),] and its progeny."
Id. at 73-74,
461 A.2d at 417-418. It held that the balance between a private
plaintiff's right to recover presumed and punitive damages without
a showing of special fault and the First Amendment rights of
"nonmedia" speakers "must be struck in favor of the private
plaintiff defamed by a nonmedia defendant."
Id. at 75, 461
A.2d at 418. Accordingly, the court held "that as a matter of
federal constitutional law, the media protections outlined in
Gertz are inapplicable to nonmedia defamation actions."
Ibid.
Recognizing disagreement among the lower courts about when the
protections of
Gertz apply, [
Footnote 1] we granted certiorari. 464 U.S. 959 (1983). We
now affirm, although for reasons different from those relied upon
by the Vermont Supreme Court.
II
As an initial matter, respondent contends that we need not
determine whether
Gertz applies in this case because the
instructions, taken as a whole, required the jury to find
"actual
Page 472 U. S. 754
malice" before awarding presumed or punitive damages. [
Footnote 2] The trial court instructed
the jury that, because the report was libelous
per se,
respondent was not required "to prove actual damages . . . since
damage and loss [are] conclusively presumed." App. 17;
accord,
id. at 19. It also instructed the jury that it could award
punitive damages only if it found "actual malice."
Id. at
20. Its only other relevant instruction was that liability could
not be established unless respondent showed "malice or lack of good
faith on the part of the Defendant."
Id. at 18. Respondent
contends that these references to "malice," "lack of good faith,"
and "actual malice" required the jury to find knowledge of falsity
or reckless disregard for the truth -- the "actual malice" of
New York Times Co. v. Sullivan, 376 U.
S. 254 (1964) -- before it awarded presumed or punitive
damages.
We reject this claim because the trial court failed to define
any of these terms adequately. It did not, for example, provide the
jury with any definition of the term "actual malice." In fact, the
only relevant term it defined was simple "malice." [
Footnote 3] And its definitions of this term
included not only the
New York Times formulation but also
other concepts such as
Page 472 U. S. 755
"bad faith" and "reckless disregard of the [statement's]
possible consequences." App.19. The instructions thus permitted the
jury to award presumed and punitive damages on a lesser showing
than "actual malice." Consequently, the trial court's conclusion
that the instructions did not satisfy
Gertz was correct,
and the Vermont Supreme Court's determination that
Gertz
was inapplicable was necessary to its decision that the trial court
erred in granting the motion for a new trial. We therefore must
consider whether
Gertz applies to the case before us.
III
In
New York Times Co. v. Sullivan, supra, the Court for
the first time held that the First Amendment limits the reach of
state defamation laws. That case concerned a public official's
recovery of damages for the publication of an advertisement
criticizing police conduct in a civil rights demonstration. As the
Court noted, the advertisement concerned "one of the major public
issues of our time."
Id. at
376 U. S. 271.
Noting that "freedom of expression
upon public questions
is secured by the First Amendment,"
id. at
376 U. S. 269
(emphasis added), and that "debate
on public issues should
be uninhibited, robust, and wide-open,"
id. at
376 U. S. 270
(emphasis added), the Court held that a public official cannot
recover damages for defamatory falsehood unless he proves that the
false statement was made with "
actual malice' -- that is, with
knowledge that it was false or with reckless disregard of whether
it was false or not," id. at 376 U. S. 280.
In later cases, all involving public issues, the Court extended
this same constitutional protection to libels of public figures,
e.g., Curtis Publishing Co. v. Butts, 388 U.
S. 130 (1967), and in one case suggested in a plurality
opinion that this constitutional rule should extend to libels of
any individual so long as the defamatory statements involved a
"matter of public or general interest," Rosenbloom v.
Metromedia, Inc., 403 U. S. 29,
403 U. S. 44
(1971) (opinion of BRENNAN,J.).
Page 472 U. S. 756
In
Gertz v. Robert Welch, Inc., 418 U.
S. 323 (1974), we held that the protections of
New
York Times did not extend as far as
Rosenbloom
suggested.
Gertz concerned a libelous article appearing in
a magazine called American Opinion, the monthly outlet of the John
Birch Society. The article in question discussed whether the
prosecution of a policeman in Chicago was part of a Communist
campaign to discredit local law enforcement agencies. The
plaintiff,
Gertz, neither a public official nor a public
figure, was a lawyer tangentially involved in the prosecution. The
magazine alleged that he was the chief architect of the "frame-up"
of the police officer and linked him to Communist activity. Like
every other case in which this Court has found constitutional
limits to state defamation laws,
Gertz involved expression
on a matter of undoubted public concern.
In
Gertz, we held that the fact that expression
concerned a public issue did not by itself entitle the libel
defendant to the constitutional protections of
New York
Times. These protections, we found, were not "justified solely
by reference to the interest of the press and broadcast media in
immunity from liability." 418 U.S. at
418 U. S. 343.
Rather, they represented "an accommodation between [First
Amendment] concern[s] and the limited state interest present in the
context of libel actions brought by public persons."
Ibid.
In libel actions brought by private persons we found the competing
interests different. Largely because private persons have not
voluntarily exposed themselves to increased risk of injury from
defamatory statements and because they generally lack effective
opportunities for rebutting such statements,
id. at
418 U. S. 345,
we found that the State possessed a "strong and legitimate . . .
interest in compensating private individuals for injury to
reputation."
Id. at
418 U. S.
348-349. Balancing this stronger state interest against
the same First Amendment interest at stake in
New York
Times, we held that a State could not allow recovery of
presumed and punitive damages absent a showing of "actual malice."
Nothing in our opinion,
Page 472 U. S. 757
however, indicated that this same balance would be struck
regardless of the type of speech involved. [
Footnote 4]
IV
We have never considered whether the
Gertz balance
obtains when the defamatory statements involve no issue of public
concern. To make this determination, we must employ the approach
approved in
Gertz and balance the State's interest in
compensating private individuals for injury to their reputation
against the First Amendment interest in protecting this type of
expression. This state interest is identical to the one weighed in
Gertz. There we found that it was "strong and legitimate."
418 U.S. at
418 U. S. 348.
A State should not lightly be required to abandon it,
"for, as Mr. Justice Stewart has reminded us, the individual's
right to the protection of his own good name
Page 472 U. S. 758
'reflects no more than our basic concept of the essential
dignity and worth of every human being -- a concept at the root of
any decent system of ordered liberty. The protection of private
personality, like the protection of life itself, is left primarily
to the individual States under the Ninth and Tenth Amendments. . .
.'
Rosenblatt v. Baer, 383 U. S. 75,
383 U. S.
92 (1966) (concurring opinion)."
Id. at
418 U. S.
341.
The First Amendment interest, on the other hand, is less
important than the one weighed in
Gertz. We have long
recognized that not all speech is of equal First Amendment
importance. [
Footnote 5] It is
speech on "
matters of public concern'"
Page 472 U. S.
759
that is "at the heart of the First Amendment's protection."
First National Bank of Boston v. Bellotti, 435 U.
S. 765, 435 U. S. 776
(1978), citing Thornhill v. Alabama, 310 U. S.
88, 310 U. S. 101
(1940). As we stated in Connick v. Myers, 461 U.
S. 138, 461 U. S. 145
(1983), this "special concern [for speech on public issues] is no
mystery":
"The First Amendment "was fashioned to assure unfettered
interchange of ideas for the bringing about of political and social
changes desired by the people."
Roth v. United States,
354 U. S. 476,
354 U. S. 484
(1957);
New York Times Co. v. Sullivan, 376 U.
S. 254,
376 U. S. 269
(1964). "[S]peech concerning public affairs is more than
self-expression; it is the essence of self-government."
Garrison v. Louisiana, 379 U. S. 64,
379 U. S. 74-75
(1964). Accordingly, the Court has frequently reaffirmed that
speech on public issues occupies the "
highest rung of the
hierarchy of First Amendment values,'" and is entitled to special
protection. NAACP v. Claiborne Hardware Co., 458 U.
S. 886, 458 U. S. 913
(1982); Carey v. Brown, 447 U. S. 455,
447 U. S.
467(1980)."
In contrast, speech on matters of purely private concern is of
less First Amendment concern.
Id. at
461 U. S.
146-147. As a number of state courts, including the
court below, have recognized, the role of the Constitution in
regulating state libel law is far more limited when the concerns
that activated
New York Times and
Gertz are
absent. [
Footnote 6] In such a
case,
Page 472 U. S. 760
"[t]here is no threat to the free and robust debate of public
issues; there is no potential interference with a meaningful
dialogue of ideas concerning self-government; and there is no
threat of liability causing a reaction of self-censorship by the
press. The facts of the present case are wholly without the First
Amendment concerns with which the Supreme Court of the United
States has been struggling."
Harley-Davidson Motorsports, Inc. v. Markley, 279 Ore.
361, 366,
568 P.2d
1359, 1363 (1977).
Accord, Rowe v. Metz, 195 Colo.
424, 426,
579 P.2d 83,
84 (1978);
Denny v. Mertz, 106 Wis.2d 636, 661,
318 N.W.2d
141, 153,
cert. denied, 459 U.S. 883 (1982).
While such speech is not totally unprotected by the First
Amendment,
see Connick v. Myers, supra, at
461 U. S. 147,
its protections are less stringent. In
Gertz, we found
that the state interest in awarding presumed and punitive damages
was not "substantial" in view of their effect on speech at the core
of First Amendment concern. 418 U.S. at
418 U. S. 349.
This interest, however,
is "substantial" relative to the
incidental effect these remedies may have on speech of
significantly less constitutional interest. The rationale of the
common law rules has been the experience and judgment of history
that
"proof of actual damage will be impossible in a great many cases
where, from the character of the defamatory words and the
circumstances of publication, it is all but certain that serious
harm has resulted in fact."
W. Prosser, Law of Torts § 112, p. 765 (4th ed.1971);
accord, Rowe v. Metz, supra, at 425-426, 579 P.2d at 84;
Note, Developments in the Law -- Defamation, 69 Harv.L.Rev. 875,
891-892 (1956). As a result, courts for centuries have allowed
juries to presume that some damage occurred from many defamatory
utterances
Page 472 U. S. 761
and publications. Restatement of Torts § 568, Comment
b, p. 162 (1938) (noting that Hale announced that damages
were to be presumed for libel as early as 1670). This rule furthers
the state interest in providing remedies for defamation by ensuring
that those remedies are effective. In light of the reduced
constitutional value of speech involving no matters of public
concern, we hold that the state interest adequately supports awards
of presumed and punitive damages -- even absent a showing of
"actual malice." [
Footnote
7]
V
The only remaining issue is whether petitioner's credit report
involved a matter of public concern. In a related context, we have
held that
"[w]hether . . . speech addresses a matter of public concern
must be determined by [the expression's] content, form, and context
. . . as revealed by the whole record."
Connick v. Myers, supra, at
461 U. S.
147-148.
Page 472 U. S. 762
These factors indicate that petitioner's credit report concerns
no public issue. [
Footnote 8]
It was speech solely in the individual interest of the speaker and
its specific business audience.
Cf. Central Hudson Gas &
Elec. Corp. v. Public Service Comm'n of New York, 447 U.
S. 557,
447 U. S. 561
(1980). This particular interest warrants no special protection
when -- as in this case the speech is wholly false and clearly
damaging to the victim's business reputation.
Cf. id. at
447 U. S. 566;
Virginia Pharmacy Bd. v. Virginia Citizens Consumer Council,
Inc., 425 U. S. 748,
425 U. S.
771-772 (1976). Moreover, since the credit report was
made available to only five subscribers, who, under the terms of
the subscription agreement, could not disseminate it further, it
cannot be said that the report involves any "strong interest in the
free flow of commercial information."
Id. at
425 U. S. 764.
There is simply no credible argument that this type of credit
reporting requires special protection to ensure that "debate on
public issues [will] be uninhibited, robust, and wide-open."
New York Times Co. v. Sullivan, 376 U.S. at
376 U. S.
270.
In addition, the speech here, like advertising, is hardy and
unlikely to be deterred by incidental state regulation.
See
Virginia Pharmacy Bd. v. Virginia Citizens Consumer Council,
Inc., 425 U.S. at
425 U. S.
771-772. It is solely motivated by the desire for
profit, which, we have noted, is a force less likely to be deterred
than others.
Ibid. Arguably, the reporting here was also
more objectively verifiable than speech deserving of greater
protection.
See ibid. In any case, the market provides a
powerful incentive to a credit reporting
Page 472 U. S. 763
agency to be accurate, since false credit reporting is of no use
to creditors. Thus, any incremental "chilling" effect of libel
suits would be of decreased significance. [
Footnote 9]
VI
We conclude that permitting recovery of presumed and punitive
damages in defamation cases absent a showing of "actual malice"
does not violate the First Amendment when the defamatory statements
do not involve matters of public concern. Accordingly, we affirm
the judgment of the Vermont Supreme Court.
It is so ordered.
[
Footnote 1]
Compare Denny v. Mertz, 106 Wis.2d 636,
318 N.W.2d
141,
cert. denied, 459 U.S. 883 (1982) (
Gertz
inapplicable to private figure suits against nonmedia defendants);
Stuempges v. Parke, Davis & Co., 297 N.W.2d
252 (Minn.1980) (same);
Rowe v. Metz, 195 Colo. 424,
579 P.2d 83
(1978) (same); and
Harley-Davidson Motorsports, Inc. v.
Markley, 279 Ore. 361,
568 P.2d
1359 (1977) (same),
with Antwerp Diamond Exchange, Inc. v.
Better Business Bureau, 130 Ariz. 523,
637 P.2d
733 (1981) (
Gertz applicable in such situations); and
Jacron Sales Co. v. Sindorf, 276 Md. 580, 350 A.2d 688
(1976) (same).
[
Footnote 2]
Respondent also argues that petitioner did not seek the
protections outlined in
Gertz before the jury instructions
were given and that the issue therefore was not preserved for
review. Since the Vermont Supreme Court considered the federal
constitutional issue properly presented and decided it, there is no
bar to our review.
See Orr v. Orr, 440 U.
S. 268, 274-275 (1979).
[
Footnote 3]
The full instruction on malice reads as follows:
"If you find that the Defendant acted in a bad faith towards the
Plaintiff in publishing the Erroneous Report,
or that
Defendant intended to injure the Plaintiff in its business,
or that it acted in a willful, wanton or reckless
disregard of the rights and interests of the Plaintiff, the
Defendant has acted maliciously and the privilege is destroyed.
Further, if the Report was made with reckless disregard of
the possible consequences,
or if it was made with the
knowledge that it was false
or with reckless disregard of
its truth or falsity, it was made with malice."
App. 18-19 (emphasis added).
[
Footnote 4]
The dissent states that "[a]t several points the Court in
Gertz makes perfectly clear [that] the restrictions of
presumed and punitive damages were to apply in all cases."
Post at
472 U.S.
785, n. 11. Given the context of
Gertz, however,
the Court could have made "perfectly clear" only that these
restrictions applied in cases involving public speech. In fact, the
dissent itself concedes that
"
Gertz . . . focused largely on defining the
circumstances under which protection of the central First Amendment
value of robust debate of
public issues should mandate
plaintiffs to show actual malice to obtain a judgment and actual
damages. . . . "
Post at
472 U. S. 777
(original emphasis).
The dissent also incorrectly states that
Gertz
"specifically held,"
post at
472 U. S. 779,
472 U. S. 793,
both
"that the award of presumed and punitive damages on less than a
showing of actual malice is not a narrowly tailored means to
achieve the legitimate state purpose of protecting the reputation
of private persons . . . ,"
post at
472 U. S. 779,
and that "unrestrained presumed and punitive damages were
unnecessarily' broad . . . in relation to the legitimate state
interests," post at 472 U. S.
793-794. Although the Court made both statements, it did
so only within the context of public speech. Neither statement
controls here. What was "not . . . narrowly tailored" or was
"`unnecessarily' broad" with respect to public speech is not
necessarily so with respect to the speech now at issue. Properly
understood, Gertz is consistent with the result we reach
today.
[
Footnote 5]
This Court on many occasions has recognized that certain kinds
of speech are less central to the interests of the First Amendment
than others. Obscene speech and "fighting words" long have been
accorded no protection.
Roth v. United States,
354 U. S. 476,
354 U. S. 483
(1957);
Chaplinsky v. New Hampshire, 315 U.
S. 568,
315 U. S.
571-572 (1942);
cf. Harisiades v. Shaughnessy,
342 U. S. 580,
342 U. S.
591-592 (1952) (advocating violent overthrow of the
Government is unprotected speech);
Near v. Minnesota ex rel.
Olson, 283 U. S. 697,
283 U. S. 716
(1931) (publication of troopship sailings during wartime may be
enjoined). In the area of protected speech, the most prominent
example of reduced protection for certain kinds of speech concerns
commercial speech. Such speech, we have noted, occupies a
"subordinate position in the scale of First Amendment values."
Ohralik v. Ohio State Bar Assn., 436 U.
S. 447,
436 U. S. 456
(1978). It also is more easily verifiable and less likely to be
deterred by proper regulation.
Virginia Pharmacy Bd. v.
Virginia Citizens Consumer Council, Inc., 425 U.
S. 748,
425 U. S.
771-772 (1976). Accordingly, it may be regulated in ways
that might be impermissible in the realm of noncommercial
expression.
Ohralik, supra, at
436 U. S. 456;
Central Hudson Gas & Elec. Corp. v. Public Service Comm'n
of New York, 447 U. S. 557
447 U. S.
562-563 (1980).
Other areas of the law provide further examples. In
Ohralik we noted that there are
"[n]umerous examples . . . of communications that are regulated
without offending the First Amendment, such as the exchange of
information about securities, corporate proxy statements, the
exchange of price and production information among competitors, and
employers' threats of retaliation for the labor activities of
employees."
436 U.S. at
436 U. S. 456
(citations omitted). Yet similar regulation of political speech is
subject to the most rigorous scrutiny.
See Brown v.
Hartlage, 456 U. S. 45,
456 U. S. 52-53
(1982);
New York Times Co. v. Sullivan, 376 U.
S. 254,
376 U. S. 279,
n.19 (1964);
Buckley v. Valeo, 424 U. S.
1,
424 U. S. 14
(1976). Likewise, while the power of the State to license lawyers,
psychiatrists, and public school teachers -- all of whom speak for
a living -- is unquestioned, this Court has held that a law
requiring licensing of union organizers is unconstitutional under
the First Amendment.
Thomas v. Collins, 323. U.S. 516
(1945);
see also Rosenbloom v. Metromedia, Inc.,
403 U. S. 29,
403 U. S. 44
(1971) (opinion of BRENNAN, J.) ("the determinant whether the First
Amendment applies to state libel actions is whether the utterance
involved concerns an issue of public or general concern").
[
Footnote 6]
As one commentator has remarked with respect to "the case of a
commercial supplier of credit information that defames a person
applying for credit" -- the case before us today --
"If the first amendment requirements outlined in
Gertz
apply, there is something clearly wrong with the first amendment or
with
Gertz."
Shiffrin, The First Amendment and Economic Regulation: Away From
a General Theory of the First Amendment, 78 Nw.U.L.Rev. 1212, 1268
(1983).
[
Footnote 7]
The dissent, purporting to apply the same balancing test that we
do today, concludes that even speech on purely private matters is
entitled to the protections of
Gertz. Post at
472 U. S. 786.
Its "balance," however, rests on a misinterpretation. In
particular, the dissent finds language in
Gertz that, it
believes, shows the State's interest to be "irrelevant."
See
post at
472 U. S. 794.
It is then an easy step for the dissent to say that the State's
interest is outweighed by even the reduced First Amendment interest
in private speech.
Gertz, however, did not say that the
state interest was "irrelevant" in absolute terms. Indeed, such a
statement is belied by
Gertz itself, for it held that
presumed and punitive damages were available under some
circumstances. 418 U.S. at
418 U. S. 349. Rather, what the
Gertz language
indicates is that the State's interest is not substantial relative
to the First Amendment interest in
public speech. This
language is thus irrelevant to today's decision.
The dissent's "balance," moreover, would lead to the protection
of all libels -- no matter how attenuated their constitutional
interest. If the dissent were the law, a woman of impeccable
character who was branded a "whore" by a jealous neighbor would
have no effective recourse unless she could prove "actual malice"
by clear and convincing evidence. This is not malice in the
ordinary sense, but in the more demanding sense of
New York
Times. The dissent would, in effect, constitutionalize the
entire common law of libel.
[
Footnote 8]
The dissent suggests that our holding today leaves all credit
reporting subject to reduced First Amendment protection. This is
incorrect. The protection to be accorded a particular credit report
depends on whether the report's "content, form, and context"
indicate that it concerns a public matter. We also do not hold, as
the dissent suggests we do,
post at
425 U. S. 787,
that the report is subject to reduced constitutional protection
because it constitutes economic or commercial speech. We discuss
such speech, along with advertising, only to show how many of the
same concerns that argue in favor of reduced constitutional
protection in those areas apply here as well.
[
Footnote 9]
The Court of Appeals for the Fifth Circuit has noted that, while
most States provide a qualified privilege against libel suits for
commercial credit reporting agencies, in those States that do not
there is a thriving credit reporting business and commercial credit
transactions are not inhibited.
Hood v. Dun & Bradstreet,
Inc., 486 F.2d 25, 32 (1973),
cert. denied, 415 U.S.
985 (1974). The court cited an empirical study comparing credit
transactions in Boise, Idaho, where there is no privilege, with
those in Spokane, Washington, where there is one. 486 F.2d at 32,
and n. 18.
CHIEF JUSTICE BURGER, concurring in the judgment.
In
Gertz v. Robert Welch, Inc., 418 U.
S. 323 (1974), contrary to well-established common law
prevailing in the states, a divided Court held that a private
plaintiff in a defamation action cannot recover for a published
falsehood unless he proves that the defendant was at least
negligent in publishing the falsehood. The Court further held that
there can be no "presumed" damages in such an action and that the
private plaintiff cannot receive "punitive" damages unless it is
established that the publication was made with "actual malice," as
defined in
New York Times Co. v. Sullivan, 376 U.
S. 254 (1964).
I dissented in
Gertz because I believed that, insofar
as the "ordinary private citizen" was concerned, 418 U.S. at
418 U. S. 355,
the Court's opinion "abandon[ed] the traditional thread,"
id. at
418 U. S.
354-355, that had been the theme of the law in this
country
Page 472 U. S. 764
up to that time. I preferred
"to allow this area of law to continue to evolve as it [had] up
to [then] with respect to private citizens rather than embark on a
new doctrinal theory which [had] no jurisprudential ancestry."
Ibid. Gertz, however, is now the law of the
land, and until it is overruled, it must, under the principle of
stare decisis, be applied by this Court.
The single question before the Court today is whether
Gertz applies to this case. The plurality opinion holds
that
Gertz does not apply because, unlike the challenged
expression in
Gertz, the alleged defamatory expression in
this case does not relate to a matter of public concern. I agree
that
Gertz is limited to circumstances in which the
alleged defamatory expression concerns a matter of general public
importance, and that the expression in question here relates to a
matter of essentially private concern. I therefore agree with the
plurality opinion to the extent that it holds that
Gertz
is inapplicable in this case for the two reasons indicated. No more
is needed to dispose of the present case.
I continue to believe, however, that
Gertz was
ill-conceived, and therefore agree with JUSTICE WHITE that
Gertz should be overruled. I also agree generally with
JUSTICE WHITE's observations concerning
New York Times Co. v.
Sullivan. New York Times, however, equates "reckless
disregard of the truth" with malice; this should permit a jury
instruction that malice may be found if the defendant is shown to
have published defamatory material which, in the exercise of
reasonable care, would have been revealed as untrue. But since the
Court has not applied the literal language of
New York
Times in this way, I agree with JUSTICE WHITE that it should
be reexamined. The great rights guaranteed by the First Amendment
carry with them certain responsibilities as well.
Consideration of these issues inevitably recalls an aphorism of
journalism that "too much checking on the facts has ruined many a
good news story."
Page 472 U. S. 765
JUSTICE WHITE, concurring in the judgment.
Until
New York Times Co. v. Sullivan, 376 U.
S. 254 (1964), the law of defamation was almost
exclusively the business of state courts and legislatures. Under
the then prevailing state libel law, the defamed individual had
only to prove a false written publication that subjected him to
hatred, contempt, or ridicule. Truth was a defense; but given a
defamatory false circulation, general injury to reputation was
presumed; special damages, such as pecuniary loss and emotional
distress, could be recovered; and punitive damages were available
if common law malice were shown. General damages for injury to
reputation were presumed and awarded because the judgment of
history was that,
"in many cases, the effect of defamatory statements is so subtle
and indirect that it is impossible directly to trace the effects
thereof in loss to the person defamed."
Restatement of Torts § 621, Comment
a, p. 314
(1938). The defendant was permitted to show that there was no
reputational injury; but at the very least, the prevailing rule was
that at least nominal damages were to be awarded for any defamatory
publication actionable
per se. This rule performed
"a vindicatory function by enabling the plaintiff publicly to
brand the defamatory publication as false. The salutary social
value of this rule is preventive in character since it often
permits a defamed person to expose the groundless character of a
defamatory rumor before harm to the reputation has resulted
therefrom "
Id. § 569, Comment
b, p. 166.
Similar rules applied to slanderous statements that were
actionable
per se. [
Footnote
2/1]
Page 472 U. S. 766
New York Times Co. v. Sullivan was the first major step
in what proved to be a seemingly irreversible process of
constitutionalizing the entire law of libel and slander. Under the
rule announced in that case, a public official suing for libel
could no longer make out his case by proving a false and damaging
publication. He could not establish liability and recover any
damages, whether presumed or actually proved, unless he proved
"malice," which was defined as a knowing falsehood or a reckless
disregard for the truth. 376 U.S. at
376 U. S. 280.
Given that proof, however, the usual damages were available,
including presumed and punitive damages. This judgment overturning
200 years of libel law was deemed necessary to implement the First
Amendment interest in "uninhibited, robust, and wide-open" debate
on public issues.
Id. at
376 U. S. 270.
Three years later, the same rule was applied to plaintiffs who were
not public officials, but who were termed public figures.
Curtis Publishing Co. v. Butts, 388 U.
S. 130,
388 U. S. 155
(1967).
In 1971, four Justices took the view that the
New York
Times rules should apply wherever a publication concerned any
manner of general or public interest, even though the plaintiff was
a private person.
Rosenbloom v. Metromedia, Inc.,
403 U. S. 29. That
view did not command a majority. But in
Gertz v. Robert Welch,
Inc., 418 U. S. 323
(1974), the Court again dealt with defamation actions by private
individuals, for the first time holding that such plaintiffs could
no longer recover by proving a false statement, no matter how
damaging it might be to reputation. They must, in addition, prove
some "fault," at least negligence.
Id. at
418 U. S. 347,
418 U. S. 350.
Even with that proof, damages were not presumed but had to be
proved.
Id. at
418 U. S. 349.
Furthermore, no punitive damages were available without proof of
New York Times malice.
Page 472 U. S. 767
418 U.S. at
418 U. S. 350.
This decision, which again purported to implement First Amendment
values, seemingly left no defamation actions free from federal
constitutional limitations.
I joined the judgment and opinion in
New York Times. I
also joined later decisions extending the
New York Times
standard to other situations. But I came to have increasing doubts
about the soundness of the Court's approach and about some of the
assumptions underlying it. I could not join the plurality opinion
in
Rosenbloom, and I dissented in
Gertz,
asserting that the common law remedies should be retained for
private plaintiffs. I remain convinced that
Gertz was
erroneously decided. I have also become convinced that the Court
struck an improvident balance in the
New York Times case
between the public's interest in being fully informed about public
officials and public affairs and the competing interest of those
who have been defamed in vindicating their reputation.
In a country like ours, where the people purport to be able to
govern themselves through their elected representatives, adequate
information about their government is of transcendent importance.
That flow of intelligence deserves full First Amendment protection.
Criticism and assessment of the performance of public officials and
of government in general are not subject to penalties imposed by
law. But these First Amendment values are not at all served by
circulating false statements of fact about public officials. On the
contrary, erroneous information frustrates these values. They are
even more disserved when the statements falsely impugn the honesty
of those men and women and hence lessen the confidence in
government. As the Court said in
Gertz:
"[T]here is no constitutional value in false statements of fact.
Neither the intentional lie nor the careless error materially
advances society's interest in 'uninhibited, robust, and wide-open'
debate on public issues."
418 U.S. at
418 U. S. 340.
Yet in
New York Times cases, the public official's
complaint will be dismissed unless he alleges and makes out a jury
case of a knowing or reckless falsehood. Absent such proof, there
will be no
Page 472 U. S. 768
jury verdict or judgment of any kind in his favor, even if the
challenged publication is admittedly false. The lie will stand, and
the public continue to be misinformed about public matters. This
will recurringly happen because the putative plaintiff's burden is
so exceedingly difficult to satisfy and can be discharged only by
expensive litigation. Even if the plaintiff sues, he frequently
loses on summary judgment or never gets to the jury because of
insufficient proof of malice. If he wins before the jury, verdicts
are often overturned by appellate courts for failure to prove
malice. Furthermore, when the plaintiff loses, the jury will likely
return a general verdict and there will be no judgment that the
publication was false, even though it was without foundation in
reality. [
Footnote 2/2] The public
is left to conclude that the challenged statement was true after
all. Their only chance of being accurately informed is measured by
the public official's ability himself to counter the lie, unaided
by the courts. That is a decidedly weak reed to depend on for the
vindication of First Amendment
Page 472 U. S. 769
interests -- "it is the rare case where the denial overtakes the
original charge. Denials, retractions, and corrections are not
hot' news, and rarely receive the prominence of the original
story." Rosenbloom, 403 U.S. at 403 U. S. 46-47
(opinion of BRENNAN, J.); Gertz, supra, at 418 U. S.
363-364 (BRENNAN, J., dissenting).
Also, by leaving the lie uncorrected, the
New York
Times rule plainly leaves the public official without a remedy
for the damage to his reputation. Yet the Court has observed that
the individual's right to the protection of his own good name is a
basic consideration of our constitutional system, reflecting
"'our basic concept of the essential dignity and worth of every
human being -- a concept at the root of any decent system of
ordered liberty.'"
Gertz, supra, at
418 U. S. 341,
quoting Rosenblatt v. Baer, 383 U. S.
75,
383 U. S. 92
(1966) (Stewart, J., concurring). The upshot is that the public
official must suffer the injury, often cannot get a judgment
identifying the lie for what it is, and has very little, if any,
chance of countering that lie in the public press.
The
New York Times rule thus countenances two evils:
first, the stream of information about public officials and public
affairs is polluted and often remains polluted by false
information; and second, the reputation and professional life of
the defeated plaintiff may be destroyed by falsehoods that might
have been avoided with a reasonable effort to investigate the
facts. In terms of the First Amendment and reputational interests
at stake, these seem grossly perverse results.
Of course, the Court in
New York Times could not have
been unaware of these realities. Despite our ringing endorsement of
"wide-open" and "uninhibited" debate, which taken literally would
protect falsehoods of all kinds, we cannot fairly be accused of
giving constitutional protection to false information as such, for
we went on to find competing and overriding constitutional
justification for our decision. The constitutional interest in the
flow of information about
Page 472 U. S. 770
public affairs was thought to be very strong, and discovering
the truth in this area very difficult, even with the best of
efforts. These considerations weighed so heavily that those who
write and speak about public affairs were thought to require some
breathing room -- that is, they should be permitted to err and
misinform the public as long as they act unknowingly and without
recklessness. If the press could be faced with possibly sizable
damages for every mistaken publication injurious to reputation, the
result would be an unacceptable degree of self-censorship, which
might prevent the occasional mistaken libel, but would also often
prevent the timely flow of information that is thought to be true
but cannot be readily verified. The press must therefore be
privileged to spread false information, even though that
information has negative First Amendment value and is severely
damaging to reputation, in order to encourage the full flow of the
truth, which otherwise might be withheld.
Gertz is subject to similar observations. Although
rejecting the
New York Times malice standard where the
plaintiff is neither a public official nor a public figure, there
the Court nevertheless deprived the private plaintiff of his common
law remedies, making recovery more difficult in order to provide a
margin for error. In doing so, the Court ruled that without proof
of at least negligence, a plaintiff damaged by the most outrageous
falsehoods would be remediless, and the lie very likely would go
uncorrected. And even if fault were proved, actual damage to
reputation would have to be shown, a burden traditional libel law
considered difficult, if not impossible, to discharge. For this
reason JUSTICE POWELL would not impose on the plaintiff the burden
of proving damages in the case now before us.
Although there was much talk in
Gertz about liability
without fault and the unfairness of presuming damages, all of this,
as was the case in
New York Times, was done in the name of
the First Amendment, purportedly to shield the press and others
writing about public affairs from possibly intimidating
Page 472 U. S. 771
damages liability. But if protecting the press from intimidating
damages liability that might lead to excessive timidity was the
driving force behind
New York Times and
Gertz, it
is evident that the Court engaged in severe overkill in both
cases.
In
New York Times, instead of escalating the
plaintiff's burden of proof to an almost impossible level, we could
have achieved our stated goal by limiting the recoverable damages
to a level that would not unduly threaten the press. Punitive
damages might have been scrutinized as Justice Harlan suggested in
Rosenbloom, supra, at
403 U. S. 77, or
perhaps even entirely forbidden. Presumed damages to reputation
might have been prohibited, or limited, as in
Gertz. Had
that course been taken and the common law standard of liability
been retained, the defamed public official, upon proving falsity,
could at least have had a judgment to that effect. His reputation
would then be vindicated; and to the extent possible, the
misinformation circulated would have been countered. He might have
also recovered a modest amount, enough perhaps to pay his
litigation expenses. At the very least, the public official should
not have been required to satisfy the actual malice standard where
he sought no damages but only to clear his name. In this way, both
First Amendment and reputational interests would have been far
better served.
We are not talking in these cases about mere criticism or
opinion, but about misstatements of fact that seriously harm the
reputation of another, by lowering him in the estimation of the
community or to deter third persons from associating or dealing
with him. Restatement of Torts § 559 (1938). The necessary
breathing room for speakers can be ensured by limitations on
recoverable damages; it does not also require depriving many public
figures of any room to vindicate their reputations sullied by false
statements of fact. It could be suggested that even without the
threat of large presumed and punitive damages awards, press
defendants' communication
Page 472 U. S. 772
will be unduly chilled by having to pay for the actual damages
caused to those they defame. But other commercial enterprises in
this country not in the business of disseminating information must
pay for the damage they cause as a cost of doing business, and it
is difficult to argue that the United States did not have a free
and vigorous press before the rule in
New York Times was
announced. In any event, the
New York Times standard was
formulated to protect the press from the chilling danger of
numerous large damages awards. Nothing in the central rationale
behind
New York Times demands an absolute immunity from
suits to establish the falsity of a defamatory misstatement about a
public figure where the plaintiff cannot make out a jury case of
actual malice.
I still believe the common law rules should have been retained
where the plaintiff is not a public official or public figure. As I
see it, the Court undervalued the reputational interest at stake in
such cases. I have also come to doubt the easy assumption that the
common law rules would muzzle the press. But even accepting the
Gertz premise that the press also needed protection in
suits by private parties, there was no need to modify the common
law requirements for establishing liability and to increase the
burden of proof that must be satisfied to secure a judgment
authorizing at least nominal damages and the recovery of additional
sums within the limitations that the Court might have set.
[
Footnote 2/3]
It is interesting that JUSTICE POWELL declines to follow the
Gertz approach in this case. I had thought that the
decision in
Gertz was intended to reach cases that involve
any false statements of fact injurious to reputation, whether the
statement is made privately or publicly and whether or not it
implicates a matter of public importance. JUSTICE POWELL, however,
distinguishes
Gertz as a case that involved a matter
Page 472 U. S. 773
of public concern, an element absent here. Wisely, in my view,
JUSTICE POWELL does not rest his application of a different rule
here on a distinction drawn between media and nonmedia defendants.
On that issue, I agree with JUSTICE BRENNAN that the First
Amendment gives no more protection to the press in defamation suits
than it does to others exercising their freedom of speech. None of
our cases affords such a distinction; to the contrary, the Court
has rejected it at every turn. [
Footnote 2/4] It should be rejected again, particularly
in this context, since it makes no sense to give the most
protection to those publishers who reach the most readers and
therefore pollute the channels of communication with the most
misinformation and do the most damage to private reputation. If
Gertz is to be distinguished from this case, on the ground
that it applies only where the allegedly false publication deals
with a matter of general or public importance, then where the false
publication does not deal with such a matter, the common law rules
would apply whether the defendant is a member of the media or other
public disseminator or a nonmedia individual publishing privately.
Although JUSTICE POWELL speaks only of the inapplicability of the
Gertz rule with respect to presumed and
Page 472 U. S. 774
punitive damages, it must be that the
Gertz requirement
of some kind of fault on the part of the defendant is also
inapplicable in cases such as this.
As I have said, I dissented in
Gertz, and I doubt that
the decision in that case has made any measurable contribution to
First Amendment or reputational values since its announcement. Nor
am I sure that it has saved the press a great deal of money. Like
the
New York Times decision, the burden that plaintiffs
must meet invites long and complicated discovery involving detailed
investigation of the workings of the press, how a news story is
developed, and the state of mind of the reporter and publisher.
See Herbert v. Lando, 441 U. S. 153
(1979). That kind of litigation is very expensive. I suspect that
the press would be no worse off financially if the common law rules
were to apply and if the judiciary was careful to insist that
damages awards be kept within bounds. A legislative solution to the
damages problem would also be appropriate. Moreover, since libel
plaintiffs are very likely more interested in clearing their names
than in damages, I doubt that limiting recoveries would deter or be
unfair to them. In any event, I cannot assume that the press, as
successful and powerful as it is, will be intimidated into
withholding news that by decent journalistic standards it believes
to be true.
The question before us is whether
Gertz is to be
applied in this case. For either of two reasons, I believe that it
should not. First, I am unreconciled to the
Gertz holding
and believe that it should be overruled. Second, as JUSTICE POWELL
indicates, the defamatory publication in this case does not deal
with a matter of public importance. Consequently, I concur in the
Court's judgment.
[
Footnote 2/1]
At the common law, slander, unlike libel, was actionable
per
se only when it dealt with a narrow range of statements: those
imputing a criminal offense, a venereal or loathsome and
communicable disease, improper conduct of a lawful business, or
unchastity of a woman. Restatement of Torts § 570 (1938). To
be actionable, all other slanderous statements required additional
proof of special damages other than an injury to reputation or
emotional distress. The special damages most often took the form of
material or pecuniary loss.
Id. § 575 and Comment
b, pp. 185-187.
[
Footnote 2/2]
If the plaintiff succeeds in proving a jury case of malice, it
may be that the jury will be asked to bring in separate verdicts on
falsity and malice. In that event, there could be a verdict in
favor of the plaintiff on falsity, but against him on malice. There
would be no judgment in his favor, but the verdict on falsity would
be a public one and would tend to set the record right and clear
the plaintiff's name.
It might be suggested that courts, as organs of the government,
cannot be trusted to discern what the truth is. But the logical
consequence of that view is that the First Amendment forbids all
libel and slander suits, for in each such suit, there will be no
recovery unless the court finds the publication at issue to be
factually false. Of course, no forum is perfect, but that is not a
justification for leaving whole classes of defamed individuals
without redress or a realistic opportunity to clear their names. We
entrust to juries and the courts the responsibility of decisions
affecting the life and liberty of persons. It is perverse indeed to
say that these bodies are incompetent to inquire into the truth of
a statement of fact in a defamation case. I can therefore discern
nothing in the Constitution which forbids a plaintiff to obtain a
judicial decree that a statement is false -- a decree he can then
use in the community to clear his name and to prevent further
damage from a defamation already published.
[
Footnote 2/3]
The Court was unresponsive to my suggestion in dissent, 418 U.S.
at
418 U. S.
391-392, that the plaintiff should be able to prove and
obtain a judgment of falsehood without having to establish any kind
of fault.
[
Footnote 2/4]
We explained in
Branzburg v. Hayes, 408 U.
S. 665 (1972) that "the informative function asserted by
representatives of the organized press" to justify greater
privileges under the First Amendment was also "performed by
lecturers, political pollsters, novelists, academic researchers,
and dramatists."
Id. at
408 U. S. 705.
From its inception, without discussing the issue, we have applied
the rule of
New York Times to nonmedia defendants.
See
New York Times, 376 U.S. at
376 U. S. 254, n.,
376 U. S. 286;
Henry v. Collins, 380 U. S. 356
(1965);
Garrison v. Louisiana, 379 U. S.
64 (1964). And this Court has made plain that the
organized press has a monopoly neither on the First Amendment nor
on the ability to enlighten.
First National Bank of Boston v.
Bellotti, 435 U. S. 765,
435 U. S. 782
(1978).
See also Pell v. Procunier, 417 U.
S. 817 (1974) (press has no independent First Amendment
right of access to prisons).
Cf. Buckley v. Valeo,
424 U.S.
1,
424 U. S. 48-49
(1976) (the idea that government can restrict the speech of some
elements of society to enhance the relative voice of others is
"wholly foreign" to the First Amendment).
JUSTICE BRENNAN, with whom JUSTICE MARSHALL, JUSTICE BLACKMUN,
and JUSTICE STEVENS join, dissenting.
This case involves a difficult question of the proper
application of
Gertz v. Robert Welch, Inc., 418 U.
S. 323 (1974), to credit reporting -- a type of speech
at some remove from that
Page 472 U. S. 775
which first gave rise to explicit First Amendment restrictions
on state defamation law -- and has produced a diversity of
considered opinions, none of which speaks for the Court. JUSTICE
POWELL's plurality opinion affirming the judgment below would not
apply the
Gertz limitations on presumed and punitive
damages to this case; rather, the three Justices joining that
opinion would hold that the First Amendment requirement of actual
malice -- a clear and convincing showing of knowing falsehood or
reckless disregard for the truth -- should have no application in
this defamation action because the speech involved a subject of
purely private concern and was circulated to an extremely limited
audience. Establishing this exception, the opinion reaffirms
Gertz for cases involving matters of public concern,
ante at
472 U. S.
756-757, and reaffirms
New York Times Co. v.
Sullivan, 376 U. S. 254
(1964), for cases in which the challenged speech allegedly libels a
public official or a public figure.
Ante at
472 U. S. 755.
JUSTICE WHITE also would affirm; he would not apply
Gertz
to this case on the ground that the subject matter of the
publication does not deal with a matter of general or public
importance.
Ante at
472 U. S. 774
(concurring in judgment). [
Footnote
3/1] THE CHIEF JUSTICE apparently agrees with JUSTICE WHITE.
Ante at
472 U. S. 764
(concurring in judgment). The four who join this opinion would
reverse the judgment of the Vermont Supreme Court. We believe that,
although protection of the type of expression at issue is
admittedly not the "central meaning of the First Amendment," 376
U.S. at
376 U. S. 273,
Gertz makes clear that the First Amendment nonetheless
requires restraints on presumed and punitive damages awards for
this
Page 472 U. S. 776
expression. The lack of consensus in approach to these
idiosyncratic facts should not, however, obscure the solid
allegiance the principles of
New York Times Co. v.
Sullivan continue to command in the jurisprudence of this
Court.
See also Bose Corp. v. Consumer's Union of the United
States, Inc., 466 U. S. 485
(1984).
I
In
New York Times Co. v. Sullivan the Court held that
the First Amendment shields all who speak in good faith from the
threat of unrestrained libel judgments for unintentionally false
criticism of a public official. Recognizing that libel law, like
all other governmental regulation of the content of speech, "can
claim no talismanic immunity from constitutional limitations [and]
must be measured by standards that satisfy the First Amendment,"
376 U.S. at
376 U. S. 269,
the Court drew from salutary common law developments,
id.
at
376 U. S. 280,
and n. 20, [
Footnote 3/2] and
unquestioned First Amendment principles,
id. at
376 U. S.
273-274, to formulate the now-familiar actual malice
test. Because the
"erroneous statement is inevitable in free debate . . . [it]
must be protected if the freedoms of expression are to have the
'breathing space' that they 'need . . . to survive.'"
New York Times Co. v. Sullivan, supra, at
Page 472 U. S. 777
376 U. S.
271-272,
quoting NAACP v. Button, 371 U.
S. 415,
371 U. S. 433
(1963);
see Bose Corp., supra, at
466 U. S. 513.
These solidly accepted principles are not at issue today.
Our First Amendment libel decisions in the last two decades have
in large measure been an effort to explore the full ramifications
of the
New York Times Co. v. Sullivan principles. Building
on the extension of actual malice to "public figure" plaintiffs in
Curtis Publishing Co. v. Butts, 388 U.
S. 130 (1967), the Court in
Rosenbloom v.
Metromedia, Inc., 403 U. S. 29
(1971), and
Gertz v. Robert Welch, Inc., supra, focused
largely on defining the circumstances under which protection of the
central First Amendment value of robust debate of public issues
should mandate plaintiffs to show actual malice to obtain a
judgment and actual damages; the Court settled on a rule requiring
actual malice as a prerequisite to recovery only in suits brought
by public officials or public figures. 418 U.S. at
418 U. S.
344-346. [
Footnote 3/3]
We have also recognized, however, that the First Amendment requires
significant protection from defamation law's chill for a range of
expression far broader than simply speech about pure political
issues.
See Time, Inc. v. Hill, 385 U.
S. 374,
385 U. S. 388
(1967) ("The guarantees for free speech and press are not the
preserve of political expression or comment upon public affairs,
essential as those are to healthy government");
cf. Abood v.
Detroit Board of Education, 431 U. S. 209,
431 U. S. 231
(1977).
Page 472 U. S. 778
Our cases since
New York Times Co. v. Sullivan have
proceeded from the general premise that all libel law implicates
First Amendment values to the extent it deters true speech that
would otherwise be protected by the First Amendment. 376 U.S. at
376 U. S. 269.
In this sense defamation law does not differ from state efforts to
control obscenity,
see Miller v. California, 413 U. S.
15,
413 U. S. 23-24
(1973), ensure loyalty,
see Speiser v. Randall,
357 U. S. 513
(1958), protect consumers,
see Virginia Pharmacy Bd. v.
Virginia Citizens Consumer Council, Inc., 425 U.
S. 748 (1976), oversee professions,
see Zauderer v.
Office of Disciplinary Counsel of Supreme Court of Ohio,
471 U. S. 626
(1985), or pursue other public welfare goals through content-based
regulation of speech.
"When we deal with the complex of strands in the web of freedoms
which make up free speech, the operation and effect of the method
by which speech is sought to be restrained must be subjected to
close analysis and critical judgment in the light of the particular
circumstances to which it is applied."
Speiser v. Randall, supra, at
357 U. S. 520.
This general proscription against unnecessarily broad content-based
regulation permeates First Amendment jurisprudence.
In libel law, no less than any other governmental effort to
regulate speech, States must therefore use finer instruments to
ensure adequate space for protected expression.
Cf. Central
Hudson Gas & Electric Corp. v. Public Service Comm'n of New
York, 447 U. S. 557,
447 U. S. 565
(1980) (restriction "may extend only so far as the interest it
serves");
Lowe v. SEC, ante at
472 U. S. 234
(WHITE, J., concurring in judgment) ("[T]he First Amendment permits
restraints on speech only when they are narrowly tailored to
advance a legitimate governmental interest"). The ready
availability and unconstrained application of presumed and punitive
damages in libel actions is too blunt a regulatory instrument to
satisfy this First Amendment principle, even when the alleged libel
does not implicate directly the type of speech at issue in
New
York Times Co. v.
Page 472 U. S. 779
Sullivan. Justice Harlan made precisely this point in
Rosenbloom:
"At a minimum,
even in the purely private libel area, I
think the First Amendment should be construed to limit the
imposition of punitive damages to those situations where actual
malice is proved. This is the typical standard employed in
assessing anyone's liability for punitive damages where the
underlying aim of the law is to compensate for harm actually
caused, . . . and no conceivable state interest could justify
imposing a harsher standard on the exercise of
those freedoms
that are given explicit protection by the First
Amendment."
403 U.S. at
403 U. S. 73
(dissenting opinion) (emphasis added).
See also id. at
403 U. S. 65;
New York Times Co. v. Sullivan, 376 U.S. at
376 U. S.
269.
Justice Harlan's perception formed the cornerstone of the
Court's analysis in
Gertz. Requiring "that state remedies
for defamatory falsehood reach no farther than is necessary to
protect the legitimate interest involved," the Court found it
"necessary to restrict defamation plaintiffs who do not prove
knowledge of falsity or reckless disregard for the truth to
compensation for actual injury." 418 U.S. at
418 U. S. 349.
The Court explained that state rules authorizing presumed and
punitive damages conferred on juries "largely uncontrolled
discretion" to assess damages "in wholly unpredictable amounts
bearing no necessary relation to the actual harm caused."
Id. at
418 U. S.
349-350. Punitive damages in particular were found to be
"
wholly irrelevant to the state interest" because "[t]hey
are not compensation for injury."
Id. at
418 U. S. 350
(emphasis added). For these reasons, the Court in
Gertz
specifically held that the award of presumed and punitive damages
on less than a showing of actual malice is not a narrowly tailored
means to achieve the legitimate state purpose of protecting the
reputation of private persons: the common law approach, said the
Court, "
unnecessarily compounds the
Page 472 U. S. 780
potential of any system of liability for defamatory falsehood to
inhibit the vigorous exercise of First Amendment freedoms."
Id. at
418 U. S. 349
(emphasis added). [
Footnote
3/4]
Thus, when an alleged libel involves criticism of a public
official or a public figure, the need to nurture robust debate of
public issues and the requirement that all state regulation of
speech be narrowly tailored coalesce to require actual malice as a
prerequisite to any recovery. When the alleged libel involves
speech that falls outside these especially important categories, we
have held that the Constitution permits States significant leeway
to compensate for actual damage to reputation. [
Footnote 3/5] The requirement of narrowly
tailored
Page 472 U. S. 781
regulatory measures, however, always mandates at least a showing
of fault and proscribes the award of presumed and punitive damages
on less than a showing of actual malice. It has remained the
judgment of the Court since
Gertz that this comprehensive
two-tiered structure best accommodates the values of the
constitutional free speech guarantee and the States' interest in
protecting reputation.
II
The question presented here is narrow. Neither the parties nor
the courts below have suggested that respondent Greenmoss Builders
should be required to show actual malice to obtain a judgment and
actual compensatory damages. Nor do the parties question the
requirement of
Gertz that respondent must show fault to
obtain a judgment and actual damages. The only question presented
is whether a jury award of presumed and punitive damages based on
less than a showing of actual malice is constitutionally
permissible.
Gertz provides a forthright negative answer.
To preserve the jury verdict in this case, therefore, the opinions
of JUSTICE POWELL and JUSTICE WHITE have cut away the protective
mantle of
Gertz.
A
Relying on the analysis of the Vermont Supreme Court, respondent
urged that this pruning be accomplished by restricting the
applicability of
Gertz to cases in which the defendant is
a "media" entity. Such a distinction is irreconcilable with the
fundamental First Amendment principle that
"[t]he inherent worth of . . . speech in terms of its capacity
for informing the public does not depend upon the identity of its
source, whether corporation, association, union, or
individual."
First National Bank of Boston
v. Bellotti, 435
Page 472 U. S. 782
U.S. 765,
435 U. S. 777
(1978). First Amendment difficulties lurk in the definitional
questions such an approach would generate. [
Footnote 3/6] And the distinction would likely be born
an anachronism. [
Footnote 3/7]
Page 472 U. S. 783
Perhaps most importantly, the argument that
Gertz
should be limited to the media misapprehends our cases. We protect
the press to ensure the vitality of First Amendment guarantees.
[
Footnote 3/8] This solicitude
implies no endorsement of the principle that speakers other than
the press deserve lesser First Amendment protection.
"In the realm of protected speech, the legislature is
constitutionally disqualified from dictating . . . the speakers who
may address a public issue."
First National Bank of Boston v. Bellotti, supra, at
435 U. S.
784-785.
See Bridges v. California,
314 U. S. 252,
314 U. S.
277-278 (1941).
The free speech guarantee gives each citizen an equal right to
self-expression and to participation in self-government.
See,
e.g., Carey v. Brown, 447 U. S. 455,
447 U. S.
459-463 (1980);
Police Department of Chicago v.
Mosley, 408 U. S. 92
(1972);
Cohen v. California, 403 U. S.
15,
403 U. S. 24
(1971);
Whitney v. California, 274 U.
S. 357,
274 U. S.
375-377 (1927) (Brandeis, J., concurring). This
guarantee also protects the rights of listeners to "the widest
possible dissemination of information from diverse and antagonistic
sources."
Associated Press v. United States, 326 U. S.
1,
326 U. S. 20
(1945). [
Footnote 3/9] Accordingly,
at least six
Page 472 U. S. 784
Members of this Court (the four who join this opinion and
JUSTICE WHITE and THE CHIEF JUSTICE) agree today that, in the
context of defamation law, the rights of the institutional media
are no greater and no less than those enjoyed by other individuals
or organizations engaged in the same activities.
See ante
at
472 U. S. 773
(opinion concurring in judgment). [
Footnote 3/10]
B
Eschewing the media/nonmedia distinction, the opinions of both
JUSTICE WHITE and JUSTICE POWELL focus primarily on the content of
the credit report as a reason for restricting the applicability of
Gertz. Arguing that at most
Gertz should protect
speech that "deals with a matter of public or general importance,"
ante at
472 U. S. 773,
JUSTICE WHITE, without analysis or explanation, decides that the
credit report at issue here falls outside this protected category.
The plurality opinion of JUSTICE POWELL offers virtually the same
conclusion with at least a garnish of substantive analysis.
Purporting to "employ the approach approved in
Gertz,"
ante at
472 U. S. 757,
JUSTICE POWELL balances the state interest in protecting private
reputation against the First Amendment interest in protecting
expression on matters not of public concern. The state interest is
found to be identical to that at stake in
Gertz. The First
Amendment interest is, however, found to be significantly weaker
because speech on public issues, such as that involved in
Gertz, receives greater constitutional protection than
speech that is not a matter of public concern.
See ante at
472 U. S.
759-760,
citing 461 U. S.
Myers,
Page 472 U. S. 785
461 U. S. 138
(1983). JUSTICE POWELL is willing to concede that such speech
receives some First Amendment protection, but on balance finds that
such protection does not reach so far as to restrain the state
interest in protecting reputation through presumed and punitive
damages awards in state defamation actions.
Ante at
472 U. S.
760-761. Without explaining what
is a "matter
of public concern," the plurality opinion proceeds to serve up a
smorgasbord of reasons why the speech at issue here is not,
ante at
472 U. S.
761-762, and on this basis affirms the Vermont courts'
award of presumed and punitive damages.
In professing allegiance to
Gertz, the plurality
opinion protests too much. As JUSTICE WHITE correctly observes,
JUSTICE POWELL departs completely from the analytic framework and
result of that case:
"Gertz was intended to reach cases that involve any false
statements . . . whether or not [they] implicat[e] a matter of
public importance."
Ante at
472 U. S. 772
(concurring in judgment). [
Footnote
3/11] Even accepting the notion that a distinction can and
should be drawn between matters
Page 472 U. S. 786
of public concern and matters of purely private concern,
however, the analyses presented by both JUSTICE POWELL and JUSTICE
WHITE fail on their own terms. Both, by virtue of what they hold in
this case, propose an impoverished definition of "matters of public
concern" that is irreconcilable with First Amendment principles.
The credit reporting at issue here surely involves a subject matter
of sufficient public concern to require the comprehensive
protections of
Gertz. Were this speech appropriately
characterized as a matter of only private concern, moreover, the
elimination of the
Gertz restrictions on presumed and
punitive damages would still violate basic First Amendment
requirements.
(1)
The five Members of the Court voting to affirm the damages award
in this case have provided almost no guidance as to what
constitutes a protected "matter of public concern." JUSTICE WHITE
offers nothing at all, but his opinion does indicate that the
distinction turns on solely the subject matter of the expression
and not on the extent or conditions of dissemination of that
expression.
Ante at
472 U. S. 773.
JUSTICE POWELL adumbrates a rationale that would appear to focus
primarily on subject matter. [
Footnote 3/12] The opinion relies on the fact that the
speech at issue was "solely in the individual interest of the
speaker and its specific
business audience,"
ante
at
472 U. S. 762
(emphasis added). Analogizing explicitly to advertising,
Page 472 U. S. 787
the opinion also states that credit reporting is "hardy" and
"solely motivated by the desire for profit."
Ibid. These
two strains of analysis suggest that JUSTICE POWELL is excluding
the subject matter of credit reports from "matters of public
concern" because the speech is predominantly in the realm of
matters of economic concern.
In evaluating the subject matter of expression, this Court has
consistently rejected the argument that speech is entitled to
diminished First Amendment protection simply because it concerns
economic matters or is in the economic interest of the speaker or
the audience.
See, e.g., Joseph Burstyn, Inc. v. Wilson,
343 U. S. 495,
343 U. S.
501-502 (1952);
American Federation of Labor v.
Swing, 312 U. S. 321,
312 U. S.
325-326 (1941);
Thornhill v. Alabama,
310 U. S. 88,
310 U. S.
101-103 (1940);
see also Abood v. Detroit Board of
Education, 431 U.S. at
431 U. S.
231-232, and n. 28.
"[O]ur cases have never suggested that expression about
philosophical, social, artistic, economic, literary, or ethical
matters -- to take a nonexhaustive list of labels -- is not
entitled to full First Amendment protection."
Id. at
431 U. S. 231.
The breadth of this protection evinces recognition that freedom of
expression is not only essential to check tyranny and foster
self-government but also intrinsic to individual liberty and
dignity and instrumental in society's search for truth.
See
Bose Corp. v. Consumers Union of United States, Inc., 466 U.S.
at
466 U. S.
503-504;
Whitney v. California, 274 U.S. at
274 U. S. 375
(Brandeis, J., concurring).
Speech about commercial or economic matters, even if not
directly implicating "the central meaning of the First Amendment,"
376 U.S. at
376 U. S. 273,
is an important part of our public discourse. The Court made clear
in the context of discussing labor relations speech in
Thornhill v. Alabama, supra:
"It is recognized now that satisfactory hours and wages and
working conditions in industry and a bargaining position which
makes these possible have an importance which is not less than the
interests of those in the business or industry directly concerned.
The health of the
Page 472 U. S. 788
present generation and of those as yet unborn may depend on
these matters, and the practices in a single factory may have
economic repercussions upon a whole region and affect widespread
systems of marketing. The merest glance at state and federal
legislation on the subject demonstrates the force of the argument
that labor relations are not matters of mere local or private
concern. Free discussion concerning the conditions in industry and
the causes of labor disputes appears to us indispensable to the
effective and intelligent use of the processes of popular
government to shape the destiny of modern industrial society."
310 U.S. at
310 U. S.
102-103. As
Thornhill suggests, the choices we
make when we step into the voting booth may well be the products of
what we have learned from the myriad of daily economic and social
phenomenon that surround us.
See id., at
310 U. S. 102
("Freedom of discussion, if it would fulfill its historic function
in this nation, must embrace all issues about which information is
needed or appropriate to enable the members of society to cope with
the exigencies of their period"). [
Footnote 3/13]
Page 472 U. S. 789
The credit reporting of Dun & Bradstreet falls within any
reasonable definition of "public concern" consistent with our
precedents. JUSTICE POWELL's reliance on the fact that Dun &
Bradstreet publishes credit reports "for profit,"
ante at
472 U. S. 762,
is wholly unwarranted. Time and again we have made clear that
speech loses none of its constitutional protection "even though it
is carried in a form that is
sold' for profit." Virginia
Pharmacy Bd., 425 U.S. at 425 U. S. 761.
See also Smith v. California, 361 U.
S. 147, 361 U. S. 150
(1959); Joseph Burstyn, Inc. v. Wilson, supra, at
343 U. S. 501.
More importantly, an announcement of the bankruptcy of a local
company is information of potentially great concern to residents of
the community where the company is located; like the labor dispute
at issue in Thornhill, such a bankruptcy "in a single
factory may have economic repercussions upon a whole region." And
knowledge about solvency and the effect and prevalence of
bankruptcy certainly would inform citizen opinions about questions
of economic regulation. It is difficult to suggest that a
bankruptcy is not a subject matter of public concern when federal
law requires invocation of judicial mechanisms to effectuate it and
makes the fact of the bankruptcy a matter of public record. See
Cox Broadcasting Corp. v. Cohn, 420 U.
S. 469 (1975).
Given that the subject matter of credit reporting directly
implicates matters of public concern, the balancing analysis the
Court today employs should properly lead to the conclusion that the
type of expression here at issue should receive First Amendment
protection from the chilling potential of unrestrained presumed and
punitive damages in defamation actions. [
Footnote 3/14]
Page 472 U. S. 790
(2)
Even if the subject matter of credit reporting were properly
considered -- in the terms of JUSTICE WHITE and JUSTICE POWELL'S
purely a matter of private discourse, this speech would fall well
within the range of valuable expression for which the First
Amendment demands protection. Much expression that does not
directly involve public issues receives significant protection. Our
cases do permit some diminution in the degree of protection
afforded one category of speech about economic or commercial
matters. "Commercial speech" -- defined as advertisements that
"[do] no more than propose a commercial transaction,"
Pittsburgh Press Co. v. Pittsburgh Comm'n on Human
Relations, 413 U. S. 376,
413 U. S. 385
(1973) -- may be more closely regulated than other types of speech.
Even commercial speech, however, receives substantial First
Amendment protection.
Zauderer v. Office of Disciplinary
Counsel of Supreme Court of Ohio, 471 U.
S. 626 (1985);
Virginia Pharmacy Bd. v. Virginia
Citizens Consumer Council, Inc., supra, at
425 U. S. 765
("So long as we preserve a predominantly free enterprise economy,
the allocation of our resources in large measure will be made
through numerous private economic decisions. . . . To this end, the
free flow of commercial information is indispensable"). Credit
reporting is not "commercial speech" as this Court has defined the
term. Even if credit reporting were so considered, it would still
be entitled to the substantial protections the First Amendment
affords that category.
See Zauderer, 471 U.S. at
471 U. S. 637;
id. at
471 U. S.
657-658 (BRENNAN, J., concurring in part and dissenting
in part). Under either view, the expression at issue in this case
should receive protection from the chilling potential of
unrestrained presumed and punitive damages awards in defamation
actions.
Page 472 U. S. 791
Our economic system is predicated on the assumption that human
welfare will be improved through informed decisionmaking. In this
respect, ensuring broad distribution of accurate financial
information comports with the fundamental First Amendment premise
that
"the widest possible dissemination of information from diverse
and antagonistic sources is essential to the welfare of the
public."
Associated Press v. United States, 326 U.S. at
326 U. S. 20. The
economic information Dun & Bradstreet disseminates in its
credit reports makes an undoubted contribution to this private
discourse essential to our wellbeing. Justice Douglas made
precisely this point:
"The language of the First Amendment does not except speech
directed at private economic decisionmaking. Certainly such speech
could not be regarded as less important than political expression.
When immersed in a free flow of commercial information, private
sector decisionmaking is at least as effective an institution as
are our various governments in furthering the social interest in
obtaining the best general allocation of resources. . . ."
"The financial data circulated by Dun & Bradstreet, Inc.,
are part of the fabric of national commercial communication."
Dun & Bradstreet, Inc. v. Grove, 404 U.
S. 898, 905-906 (1971) (Douglas, J., dissenting from
denial of certiorari). Justice Douglas further noted that
"[p]resumably the credit reports published by the petitioner
facilitate through the price system the improvement of human
welfare at least as much as did the underlying disagreement in our
most recent libel opinion,
Rosenbloom v. Metromedia, Inc.,
403 U. S.
29 (1971), arising out of a squabble over whether a
vendor had sold obscene magazines."
Id. at 905, n. 9.
The credit reports of Dun & Bradstreet bear few of the
earmarks of commercial speech that might be entitled to somewhat
less rigorous protection. In every case in which we have permitted
more extensive state regulation on the basis of a commercial speech
rationale the speech being regulated
Page 472 U. S. 792
was pure advertising -- an offer to buy or sell goods and
services or encouraging such buying and selling. [
Footnote 3/15] Credit reports are not commercial
advertisements for a good or service or a proposal to buy or sell
such a product. We have been extremely chary about extending the
"commercial speech" doctrine beyond this narrowly circumscribed
category of advertising because often vitally important speech will
be uttered to advance economic interests and because the profit
motive making such speech hardy dissipates rapidly when the speech
is not advertising.
Compare Central Hudson Gas & Electric
Corp. v. Public Service Comm'n of New York, 447 U.
S. 557 (1980),
with Consolidated Edison Co. v.
Public Service Comm'n of New York, 447 U.
S. 530 (1980).
It is worth noting in this regard that the common law of most
States, although apparently not of Vermont, 143 Vt. 66, 76,
461 A.2d 414,
419 (1983), recognizes a qualified privilege for reports like that
at issue here.
See Maurer, Common Law Defamation and the
Fair Credit Reporting Act, 72 Geo. L.J. 95, 99-105 (1983). The
privilege typically precludes recovery for false and defamatory
credit information without a showing of bad faith or malice, a
standard of proof which is often defined according to the
New
York Times formulation.
See, e.g., Datacon, Inc. v. Dun
& Bradstreet, Inc., 465 F.
Supp. 706, 708 (ND Tex.1979). The common law thus recognizes
that credit reporting is quite susceptible to libel's chill; this
accumulated learning is worthy of respect.
Page 472 U. S. 793
Even if JUSTICE POWELL's characterization of the credit
reporting at issue here were accepted in its entirety, his opinion
would have done no more than demonstrate that this speech is the
equivalent of commercial speech. The opinion, after all, relies on
analogy to advertising. Credit reporting is said to be hardy,
motivated by desire for profit, and relatively verifiable.
Ante at
472 U. S. 762.
But this does not justify the elimination of restrictions on
presumed and punitive damages. State efforts to regulate commercial
speech in the form of advertising must abide by the requirement
that the regulatory means chosen be narrowly tailored so as to
avoid any unnecessary chilling of protected expression.
See
Zauderer, supra; Virginia Pharmacy Bd. v. Virginia Citizens
Consumer Council, Inc., supra; Central Hudson Gas & Electric
Corp. v. Public Service Comm'n of New York, supra. [
Footnote 3/16]
The Court in
Gertz specifically held that unrestrained
presumed and punitive damages were "unnecessarily" broad,
Page 472 U. S. 794
418 U.S. at
418 U. S. 350,
in relation to the legitimate state interests. Indeed,
Gertz held that in a defamation action punitive damages,
designed to chill and not to compensate, were "
wholly
irrelevant" to furtherance of any valid state interest.
Ibid. The Court did not reach these conclusions by
weighing the strength of the state interest against the strength of
the First Amendment interest. Rather, the Court recognized and
applied the principle that regulatory measures that chill protected
speech be no broader than necessary to serve the legitimate state
interest asserted. The plurality opinion today recognizes, as it
must, that the state interest at issue here is identical to that at
issue in
Gertz. What was "irrelevant" in
Gertz
must still be irrelevant, and the requirement that the regulatory
means be no broader than necessary is no less applicable even if
the speech is simply the equivalent of commercial speech. Thus,
unrestrained presumed and punitive damages for this type of speech
must run afoul of First Amendment guarantees. [
Footnote 3/17]
(3)
Even if not at "the essence of self-government,"
Garrison v.
Louisiana, 379 U. S. 64,
379 U. S. 74-75
(1964), the expression at issue in this case is important to both
our public discourse and our private welfare. That its motivation
might be the economic interest of the speaker or listeners does not
diminish its First Amendment value.
See
Consolidated Edison
Co.
Page 472 U. S. 795
v. Public Service Comm'n of New York, 447 U.
S. 530 (1980). Whether or not such speech is
sufficiently central to First Amendment values to require actual
malice as a standard of liability, this speech certainly falls
within the range of speech that
Gertz sought to protect
from the chill of unrestrained presumed and punitive damages
awards. [
Footnote 3/18]
Of course, the commercial context of Dun & Bradstreet's
reports is relevant to the constitutional analysis insofar as it
implicates the strong state interest "in protecting consumers and
regulating commercial transactions,"
Ohralik v. Ohio State Bar
Assn., 436 U. S. 447,
436 U. S. 460
(1978).
Cf. Bolger v. Young Drug Products Corp.,
463 U. S. 60,
463 U. S. 81
(1983) (STEVENS, J., concurring in judgment). The special harms
caused by inaccurate credit reports, the lack of public
sophistication about or access to such reports, and the fact that
such reports by and large contain statements that are fairly
readily susceptible of verification, all may justify
appropriate
Page 472 U. S. 796
regulation designed to prevent the social losses caused by false
credit reports. [
Footnote 3/19]
And in the libel context, the States' regulatory interest in
protecting reputation is served by rules permitting recovery for
actual compensatory damages upon a showing of fault. Any further
interest in deterring potential defamation through case-by-case
judicial imposition of presumed and punitive damages awards on less
than a showing of actual malice simply exacts too high a toll on
First Amendment values. Accordingly, Greenmoss Builders should be
permitted to recover for any actual damage it can show resulted
from Dun & Bradstreet's negligently false credit report, but
should be required to show actual malice to receive presumed or
punitive damages. Because the jury was not instructed in accordance
with these principles, we would reverse and remand for further
proceedings not inconsistent with this opinion.
[
Footnote 3/1]
JUSTICE WHITE also ventures some modest proposals for
restructuring the First Amendment protections currently afforded
defendants in defamation actions. JUSTICE WHITE agrees with
New
York Times Co. v. Sullivan, however, that the breathing space
needed to ensure the robust debate of public issues essential to
our democratic society is impermissibly threatened by unrestrained
damages awards for defamatory remarks.
Ante at
472 U. S.
770-772 (opinion concurring in judgment).
[
Footnote 3/2]
The principles were expressed as early as 1788 in an opinion of
the Pennsylvania Supreme Court:
"What then is the meaning of the bill of rights, and
Constitution of Pennsylvania, when they declare, 'That the freedom
of the press shall not be restrained,' and"
"that the printing presses shall be free to every person who
undertakes to examine the proceedings of the legislature or any
part of the government?"
". . . [T]hey give to every citizen a right of investigating the
conduct of those who are entrusted with the public business. . . .
The true liberty of the press is amply secured by permitting every
man to publish his opinions; but it is due to the peace and dignity
of society to enquire into the motives of such publications, and to
distinguish between those which are meant for use and reformation,
and with an eye solely to the public good, and those which are
intended merely to delude and defame. To the latter description, it
is impossible that any good government should afford protection and
impunity."
Respublica v.
Oswald, 1 Dall. 319,
1 U.S. 325 (footnotes omitted).
[
Footnote 3/3]
A plurality in
Rosenbloom would have applied the actual
malice standard of liability when the alleged libel concerned
matters of "public or general interest," irrespective of the status
of the plaintiff. 403 U.S. at
403 U. S. 43
(opinion of BRENNAN, J.). In
Gertz the Court rejected the
Rosenbloom plurality's "public or general interest"
approach. That approach was thought unacceptably to impair the
reputational interests of private individuals, who, unlike public
officials or public figures, neither assume the risk of rough
treatment by entering the public arena nor have ready access to the
media to rebut false charges. 418 U.S. at
418 U. S.
344-345. It was also thought to
"occasion the additional difficulty of forcing state and federal
judges to decide on an
ad hoc basis which publications
address issues of 'general or public interest.'"
Id. at
418 U. S. 346
(citation omitted).
[
Footnote 3/4]
Since the decision in
Gertz, we have applied its
reasoning with respect to damages in excess of compensation for
actual harm in other areas of the law.
See, e.g., Electrical
Workers v. Foust, 442 U. S. 42,
442 U. S. 48-52
(1979);
Newport v. Fact Concerts, Inc., 453 U.
S. 247,
453 U. S.
270-271 (1981). These cases, like
Gertz,
recognize that
"the alleged deterrence achieved by punitive damages awards is
likely outweighed by the costs -- such as the encouragement of
unnecessary litigation and the chilling of desirable conduct --
flowing from the rule, at least when the standards on which the
awards are based are ill-defined."
Smith v. Wade, 461 U. S. 30,
461 U. S. 59
(1983) (REHNQUIST, J., dissenting).
See id. at
461 U. S. 46-47
(Court opinion) (noting prevailing view that punitive damages may
only be awarded for "
conduct that is outrageous, because of the
defendant's evil motive or his reckless indifference to the rights
of others,'" quoting Restatement (Second) of Torts §
908(2) (1979) (emphasis deleted)); 461 U.S. at 461 U. S. 93-94
(O'CONNOR, J., dissenting); Silkwood v. Kerr-McGee Corp.,
464 U. S. 238,
464 U. S.
244-245 (1984); id. at 464 U. S.
260-261 (BLACKMUN, J., dissenting); id. at
464 U. S. 276
(POWELL, J., dissenting).
[
Footnote 3/5]
Such speech might at times involve issues of public or general
interest within the meaning of
Rosenbloom and thus
implicate important First Amendment interests. To justify this
cost, the Court in
Gertz held that the State had an
enhanced interest in protecting private reputation and cited the
independent First Amendment difficulties inherent in case-by-case
judicial determination of whether speech concerns a matter of
public interest. 418 U.S. at
418 U. S.
344-346.
See n.
472
U.S. 749fn3/3|>3,
supra. The decision in
Gertz is also susceptible of an alternative justification.
Speech allegedly defaming a private person will generally be far
less likely to implicate matters of public importance than will
speech allegedly defaming public officials or public figures. In
light of the problems inherent in case-by-case judicial
determination of what is in the public interest, the Court's result
could be explained as a decision that the cost of case-by-case
evaluation could be avoided without significant chilling of speech
involving matters of public importance.
[
Footnote 3/6]
An attempt to characterize petitioner Dun & Bradstreet
illustrates the point. Like an account of judicial proceedings in a
newspaper, magazine, or news broadcast, a statement in petitioner's
reports that a particular company has filed for bankruptcy is a
report of a timely news event conveyed to members of the public by
a business organized to collect and disseminate such information.
Thus it is not obvious why petitioner should find less protection
in the First Amendment than do established print or electronic
media. The Vermont Supreme Court nonetheless characterized
petitioner as a nonmedia defendant entitled to less protection
because it is
"in the business of selling financial information to a limited
number of subscribers who have paid substantial fees for [its]
services."
143 Vt. 66, 73,
461 A.2d 414,
417 (1983). The court added that
"[t]here is a clear distinction between a publication which
disseminates news for public consumption and one which provides
specialized information to a selective, finite audience."
Ibid.
No clear line consistent with First Amendment principles can be
drawn on the basis of these criteria. That petitioner's information
is "specialized" or that its subscribers pay "substantial fees"
hardly distinguishes these reports from articles in many
publications that would surely fall on the "media" side of the line
the Vermont Supreme Court seeks to draw. Few published statements
are of universal interest, and few publications are distributed
without charge. Much fare of any metropolitan daily is specialized
information for which a selective, finite audience pays a fee. Nor
is there any reason to treat petitioner differently than a more
widely circulated publication because it has "a limited number of
subscribers." Indeed, it would be paradoxical to increase
protection to statements injurious to reputation as the size of
their audience, and hence their potential to injure, grows.
Cf.
Keeton v. Hustler Magazine, Inc., 465 U.
S. 770,
465 U. S. 781
(1984).
[
Footnote 3/7]
Owing to transformations in the technological and economic
structure of the communications industry, there has been an
increasing convergence of what might be labeled "media" and
"nonmedia." Pool, The New Technologies: Promise of Abundant
Channels at Lower Cost, in What's News: The Media in American
Society 81, 87 (1981).
See also I. Pool, Technologies of
Freedom (1983); U.S. Federal Trade Commission, Media Policy
Session: Technology and Legal Change (1979); Subcommittee on
Telecommunications, Consumer Protection, and Finance of the House
Committee on Energy and Commerce, Telecommunications in Transition:
The Status of Competition in the Telecommunications Industry, 97th
Cong., 1st Sess. (Comm. Print 1981).
[
Footnote 3/8]
See, e.g., Minneapolis Star & Tribune Co. v. Minnesota
Comm'r of Revenue, 460 U. S. 575,
460 U. S. 585
(1983);
Columbia Broadcasting System, Inc. v. FCC,
453 U. S. 367,
453 U. S. 395
(1981);
Miami Herald Publishing Co. v. Tornillo,
418 U. S. 241
(1974);
Branzburg v. Hayes, 408 U.
S. 665,
408 U. S. 707
(1972);
New York Times Co. v. United States, 403 U.
S. 713 (1971);
Mills v. Alabama, 384 U.
S. 214,
384 U. S.
218-219 (1966);
Grosjean v. American Press Co.,
Inc., 297 U. S. 233,
297 U. S. 250
(1936).
See also Herbert v. Lando, 441 U.
S. 153,
441 U. S.
180-199 (1979) (BRENNAN, J., dissenting in part);
Saxbe v. Washington Post Co., 417 U.
S. 843,
417 U. S. 850
(1974) (POWELL, J., dissenting);
Pittsburgh Press Co. v.
Pittsburgh Comm'n on Human Relations, 413 U.
S. 376,
413 U. S. 393
(1973) (BURGER, C.J., dissenting);
Red Lion Broadcasting Co. v.
FCC, 395 U. S. 367,
395 U. S. 390
(1969);
Time, Inc. v. Hill, 385 U.
S. 374,
385 U. S. 389
(1967); Stewart, "Or of the Press," 26 Hastings L.J. 631
(1975).
[
Footnote 3/9]
In light of the "increasingly prominent role of mass media in
our society, and the awesome power it has placed in the hands of a
select few,"
Gertz, 418 U.S. at
418 U. S. 402
(WHITE, J., dissenting), protection for the speech of nonmedia
defendants is essential to ensure a diversity of perspectives.
See J. Barron, Freedom of the Press for Whom? (1973).
"[U]ninhibited, robust and wide-open" debate,
New York Times
Co. v. Sullivan, 376 U.S. at
376 U. S. 270,
among nonmedia speakers is as essential to the fostering and
development of an individual's political thought as is such debate
in the mass media.
See J. Klapper, The Effects of Mass
Communications (1960).
[
Footnote 3/10]
JUSTICE POWELL's opinion does not expressly reject the
media/nonmedia distinction, but does expressly decline to apply
that distinction to resolve this case.
[
Footnote 3/11]
One searches
Gertz in vain for a single word to support
the proposition that limits on presumed and punitive damages
obtained only when speech involved matters of public concern.
Gertz could not have been grounded in such a premise.
Distrust of placing in the courts the power to decide what speech
was of public concern was precisely the rationale
Gertz
offered for rejecting the
Rosenbloom plurality approach.
418 U.S. at
418 U. S. 346.
It would have been incongruous for the Court to go on to
circumscribe the protection against presumed and punitive damages
by reference to a judicial judgment as to whether the speech at
issue involved matters of public concern. At several points, the
Court in
Gertz makes perfectly clear the restrictions of
presumed and punitive damages were to apply in all cases.
Id. at
418 U. S. 346,
418 U. S.
349-350.
Indeed, JUSTICE POWELL's opinion today is fairly read as
embracing the approach of the
Rosenbloom plurality to
deciding when the Constitution should limit state defamation law.
The limits imposed, however, are less stringent than those suggest
by the
Rosenbloom plurality. Under the approach of today's
plurality, speech about matters of public or general interest
receives only the
Gertz protections against unrestrained
presumed and punitive damages, not the full
New York Times Co.
v. Sullivan protections against any recovery absent a showing
of actual malice.
[
Footnote 3/12]
JUSTICE POWELL also appears to rely in part on the fact that
communication was limited and confidential.
Ante at
472 U. S. 762.
Given that his analysis also relies on the subject matter of the
credit report,
ante at
472 U. S.
761-762, it is difficult to decipher exactly what role
the nature and extent of dissemination plays in JUSTICE POWELL's
analysis. But because the subject matter of the expression at issue
is properly understood as a matter of public concern,
see
infra, at
472 U. S.
791-793, it may well be that this element of
confidentiality is crucial to the outcome as far as JUSTICE
POWELL's opinion is concerned. In other words, it may be that
JUSTICE POWELL thinks this particular expression could not
contribute to public welfare because the public generally does not
receive it. This factor does not suffice to save the analysis.
See n.
472
U.S. 749fn3/18|>18,
infra.
[
Footnote 3/13]
Similarly, we have rejected the arguments for denying or
restricting First Amendment protection of advertising on the ground
that advertising is not a matter of public concern. Recognizing
that even pure advertising may well be affected with a public
interest, we have stated that
"the free flow of commercial information is indispensable . . .
to the formation of intelligent opinions as to how [our economic]
system ought to be regulated or altered."
Virginia Pharmacy Bd. v. Virginia Citizens Consumer Council,
Inc., 425 U. S. 748,
425 U. S. 765
(1976).
See also Bigelow v. Virginia, 421 U.
S. 809,
421 U. S. 822
(1975) ("Viewed in its entirety the [abortion] advertisement
conveyed information of potential interest and value to a diverse
audience -- not only to readers possibly in need of the services
offered"). The potential political aspect of attempts to influence
consumer preferences has also been recognized.
See Metromedia,
Inc. v. San Diego, 453 U. S. 490,
453 U. S.
538-539 (1981) (BRENNAN, J., concurring in judgment)
("May the city decide that a United Automobile Workers billboard
with the message
Be a patriot -- do not buy
Japanese-manufactured cars' is `commercial' and therefore forbid
it?"). The greater state latitude for regulating commercial
advertising is instead a function of "greater objectivity and
hardiness." Virginia Pharmacy Bd. v. Virginia Citizens Consumer
Council, Inc., supra, at 425 U. S. 772,
n. 24.
[
Footnote 3/14]
JUSTICE POWELL purports to draw from
Connick v. Myers,
461 U. S. 138
(1983), a test for distinguishing matters of public concern from
matters of private concern. This reliance perpetuates a definition
of "public concern" wholly out of accord with out consistent
precedents and with the common-law understanding of the concept.
See id. at
461 U. S. 165,
n. 5 (BRENNAN, J., dissenting). Moreover,
Connick
explicitly limited its distinction between public and private
concern to the "context" of a government employment situation.
Id. at
461 U. S. 148,
and n. 8.
[
Footnote 3/15]
See, e.g., Zauderer v. Office of Disciplinary Counsel of
Supreme Court of Ohio, 471 U. S. 626
(1985);
Bolger v. Young Products Corp., 463 U. S.
60 (1983) (contraceptive advertising);
In re R.
M.J., 455 U. S. 191
(1982) (lawyer advertising);
Metromedia, Inc. v. San
Diego, 453 U. S. 490
(1981) (commercial billboard advertising);
Central Hudson Gas
& Electric Corp. v. Public Service Comm'n of New York,
447 U. S. 557
(1980) (advertising of electricity);
Friedman v. Rogers,
440 U. S. 1 (1979)
(optometrist advertising);
Ohralik v. Ohio State Bar
Assn., 436 U. S. 447
(1978) (lawyer's solicitation of business);
Bates v. State Bar
of Arizona, 433 U. S. 350
(1977) (lawyer advertising).
[
Footnote 3/16]
Indeed JUSTICE POWELL has chosen a particularly inapt set of
facts as a basis for urging a return to the common law. Though the
individual's interest in reputation is certainly at the core of
notions of human dignity,
ante at
472 U. S.
757-758,
citing Rosenblatt v. Baer,
383 U. S. 75,
383 U. S. 92
(1966) (Stewart, J., concurring);
see Paul v. Davis,
424 U. S. 693,
424 U. S. 714
(1976) (BRENNAN, J., dissenting), the reputational interest at
stake here is that of a corporation. Similarly, that this speech is
solely commercial in nature undercuts the argument that presumed
damages should be unrestrained in actions like this one because
actual harm will be difficult to prove. If the credit report is
viewed as commercial expression, proving that actual damages
occurred is relatively easy. For instance, an alleged libel
concerning a bank's customer may cause the bank to lower the credit
limit or raise the interest rate charged that customer. The
commercial context does not increase the need for presumed damages,
but if anything reduces the need to presume harm. At worst, the
commercial damages caused by such action should be no more
difficult to ascertain than many other traditional elements of tort
damages.
See, e.g., Russell v. City of Wildwood, 428 F.2d
1176, 1181 (CA3 1970) (future earnings);
Seffert v. Los Angeles
Transit Line, 56 Cal. 2d
498, 509, 364 P.2d 337, 344 (1961) (Traynor, J., dissenting)
(pain and suffering).
[
Footnote 3/17]
JUSTICE POWELL's analysis fails to apply the requirement that
regulation be narrowly tailored. At one point the opinion
reads:
"This particular interest [in credit reporting] warrants no
special protection when . . . the speech is wholly false and
clearly damaging to the victim's business reputation."
Ante at
472 U. S. 762.
The point, of course, is not that false speech intrinsically
deserves protection,
see Gertz, 418 U.S. at
418 U. S. 340,
but that the burdening of unintentional false speech potentially
chills truthful speech. Thus, the state interest in compensating
injury resulting from false speech must be vindicated by means that
are narrowly tailored to avoid this deleterious result.
[
Footnote 3/18]
JUSTICE POWELL also relies in part on the fact that the
expression had a limited circulation and was expressly kept
confidential by those who received it. Because the subject matter
of the expression at issue in this case would clearly receive the
comprehensive protections of
Gertz were the speech
publicly disseminated, this factor of confidential circulation to a
limited number of subscribers is perhaps properly understood as the
linchpin of JUSTICE POWELL's analysis.
See ante at
472 U. S. 762
(because of confidentiality "it cannot be said that the report
involves any
strong interest in the free flow of commercial
information'") (plurality opinion) (citation omitted). See
also n. 472
U.S. 749fn3/12|>12, supra.
This argument does not save the analysis. The assertion that the
limited and confidential circulation might make the expression less
a matter of public concern is dubious on its own terms and flatly
inconsistent with our decision in
Givhan v. Western Line
Consolidated School Dist., 439 U. S. 410
(1979). Perhaps more importantly, Dun & Bradstreet doubtless
provides thousands of credit reports to thousands of subscribers
who receive the information pursuant to the same strictures imposed
on the recipients in this case. As a systemic matter, therefore,
today's decision diminishes the free flow of information because
Dun & Bradstreet will generally be made more reticent in
providing information to all its subscribers.
[
Footnote 3/19]
See Maurer, Common Law Defamation and the Fair Credit
Reporting Act, 72 Geo. L.J. 95, 126 (1983):
"Under
Gertz, plaintiffs may be compensated for actual
damages upon establishing the fault of the defendant; to obtain
punitive damages, a plaintiff must demonstrate malice. Sections
1681o and 1681n [of the Fair Credit Reporting Act] are consistent
with these constitutional principles. Section 1681o provides for
recovery of actual damages upon a showing of negligence, which
presumably satisfies the
Gertz requirement of fault.
Section 1681n authorizes punitive damages for willful violation of
the Act. Whether section 1681n is equivalent to
Gertz's
malice standard depends on whether a court would consider it to be
possible to fail willfully to follow reasonable procedures and yet
not manifest reckless disregard for the truth. Such a fine
distinction appears unworkable as a categorical test, so that
section 1681n would likely be regarded as harmonious with the
principles of
Gertz. Thus, the Act appears to provide the
degree of protection for commercial speech currently required under
first amendment doctrine"
(footnotes omitted).